ebook img

Orange Juice and Agent Orange - Arcade PDF

14 Pages·2011·0.14 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Orange Juice and Agent Orange - Arcade

Orange Juice and Agent Orange Bruce Robbins . . . how can you tell the difference between orange juice and agent orange if the same massive system connects them at levels outside your comprehension? Don DeLillo, Underworld THE PHRASE FROM DON DELILLO THAT I HAVE TAKEN AS MY TITLE spontaneously re-created itself at the birthplace of this collection of articles, a conference held at the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign in March 2006 and entitled “States of Welfare.” No conscious allusion was made to Don DeLillo, yet his question was suddenly present in the room, and in very nearly his exact words. It seemed like a message from the massive system itself. And it was so taken, I think, even by those of us, like myself, who have our doubts about paranoia as the imagination’s default setting and who thus wonder (as DeLillo seems to wonder in Underworld) whether we can be sure there exists a single system that connects orange juice and Agent Orange at a level beyond our comprehension. Even as a cause of wonderment, however, the uncanny repetition of words seemed to put us on notice that from this time forward we would be talking about a new and urgent topic. Some of us had come to the conference prepared to take part in ongoing conversations: the heritage of the Enlightenment and whether it should or could be left behind (would there be a rematch between Foucault and Habermas?), or the stance of the academic Left toward liberal- ism in a time when, outside the academy, liberalism could plausibly be seen as marginalized and even stigmatized rather than as complacently empowered. Once the orange-colored words had been linked, however, what we got instead was an exercise in defamiliarization. For neither Fou- Robbins, Bruce. “Orange Juice and Agent Orange.” Occasion: Interdisciplinary Studies in the Humanities v. 2 (December 20, 2010), http://occasion.stanford.edu/node/41. 2 OCCASION cault nor Habermas offered much guidance on the questions we suddenly found before us. Does the value of action at the level of the nation depend absolutely on how that action looks from a broader, transnational perspective? If the “system” widely assumed to connect the two indeed exists only at a level beyond our comprehension, then would not their identification belong to the realm of theology rather than to that of secular ethics? Is there a nontheological way of nego- tiating the relationship between domestic governmentality and the uses of governmental power (largely violent ones) in the space beyond the nation? Is there a relationship that does not as- sume their ethical equivalence? The phrase “orange juice and Agent Orange,” which crystallized these questions, was a col- laborative effort. The orange juice part of it came from my plenary lecture, which talked about Carolyn Steedman’s Landscape for a Good Woman.1 As I read it, Steedman’s memoir makes a backhanded but nonetheless compelling and indeed exemplary case for the welfare state. This is not a case that Steedman seems eager to make. In her book’s opening scene, a memory of child- hood trauma, a representative of the welfare state, a caseworker, or “health visitor,” humiliates the family and provokes the four-year-old Carolyn to assume a defiant sense of her class identity. It is something of a surprise, therefore, to read the generous assessment of the welfare state that follows: “It was a considerable achievement for a society to pour so much milk and so much or- ange juice, so many vitamins, down the throats of its children, and for the height and weight of those children to outstrip the measurements of only a decade before; and this remains an achievement in spite of the fact that the statistics of healthy and intelligent childhood were stretched along the curve of achievement, and only a few were allowed to travel through the nar- row gate at the age of eleven, towards the golden city” (122). The milk and orange juice are mentioned as part of Steedman’s defense of “state interven- tion in children’s lives” in the 1950s—interventions in the lives of families as well, of course, and interventions that took the sometimes very disagreeable shape of health visitors at the door. As she gets toward the end of the book, Steedman appears to forget the health visitor scene and how awful she had found it. State intervention was “experienced, by me at least,” she writes, “as entirely beneficent.” One of the few who “were allowed to travel through the narrow gate . . . to- wards the golden city,” Steedman knows it is not fair that the travelers were so few. Yet she in- sists, I think quite properly, that it was indeed an achievement for society in its newly and self- consciously organized political form to have done so much for so many. Her account of what it felt like to be on the receiving end of the state’s attention in the years after the health visitor is no less convincing than the opening scene: “The calculated, dictated fairness of the ration book went on into the new decade, and we spent a lot of time after we moved from Hammersmith to Streatham Hill, picking up medicine bottles of orange juice and jars of Virol from the baby clinic BRUCE ROBBINS is Old Dominion Foundation Professor of the Humanities in the Department of English and Comparative Literature at Columbia University. He has also taught at the universities of Geneva and Lausanne in Switzerland and at Rutgers University, New Brunswick, NJ, and has held visiting positions at Harvard, Cornell, and New York University. His most recent book is Upward Mobility and the Common Good (2007). He is also the author of Feeling Global: Internationalism in Distress (1999), Secular Vocations: Intellectuals, Professionalism, Culture (1993), and The Servant's Hand: English Fiction from Below (1986) and is coauthor of the Longman Anthology of World Literature (2003). He has edited Intellectuals: Aesthetics, Politics, Academics (1990) and The Phantom Public Sphere (1993) and coedited (with Pheng Cheah) Cosmopolitics: Thinking and Feeling beyond the Nation (1998). He was coeditor of the journal Social Text from 1991 to 2000 and is presently on the editorial board of boundary 2. He is coeditor (with David Palumbo-Liu and Nirvana Tanoukhi) of a forthcoming collection of essays, Immanuel Wallerstein and the Problem of the World. His current research is on versions of cosmopolitanism. 1 Carolyn Steedman, Landscape for a Good Woman (London: Virago, 1986). ROBBINS | ORANGE JUICE AND AGENT ORANGE 3 for my sister. I think I would be a very different person now if orange juice and milk and dinners at school hadn’t told me, in a covert way, that I had a right to exist, was worth something” (121– 22). Though Steedman begins in anger against a representative of the state’s intervention in chil- dren’s lives, she ends in no doubt that it is only such interventions that allowed her to feel that she herself “had a right to exist, was worth something.” In my lecture I went on to suggest that despite the memoir’s traumatic opening, Steedman herself finally becomes an ambivalent representative of the welfare state, a kind of intellectual health visitor.2 The work she describes herself doing, having benefited from state scholarships and become a state-supported academic historian, is visibly continuous with the work of “visit- ing” and in a sense trying to rescue the working class, including women like her mother, her sis- ter, and herself as a child. After her fashion, she too is now distributing milk and orange juice. No one familiar with her career could believe that this statelike labor is either negligible or merely complicit in a structure of social subordination. Enter our title’s second phrase. In the course of a witty and generous response to this lec- ture, Cary Nelson raised the legitimate and perhaps inevitable question of whether my focus on welfare did not obscure the state’s other, less nurturing functions, like imprisoning people of color on a massive scale and, of course, making war. War was on everyone’s mind. We were a few days from the third anniversary of the U.S. bombing and invasion of Iraq. The Vietnam era term “quagmire,” initially hushed up by a supine media, had already returned with a vengeance. In talking so appreciatively about orange juice, Nelson suggested, we should not forget about Agent Orange. The phrase was immediately picked up by other speakers and became, in my eyes at least, the central animating theme of a very animated conference. The proceedings were not taped, and the present collection makes no effort to reproduce them—indeed, various contributions are entirely new. But the volume does take its inspiration from the passionate intelligence and variety of perspectives provoked by this lapidary formulation: on the one hand, horrifying mili- tary barbarism against enemy civilians and even toward the state’s own veterans (accountability for Agent Orange has by no means been resolved to everyone’s satisfaction); on the other hand, the premise that even in this international context there was reason to support the state’s agency in sheltering its own citizens and residents from the extreme cruelties of the market— to sup- port, that is, the state’s real or potential benevolence. The organizers of the conference, Lauren Goodlad and Michael Rothberg, were by no means neutral in this debate. Their premise was that the humanities in general and literary criti- cism in particular have for too long delayed a necessary engagement with the agency of the state. This agency needed to be acknowledged for its formative role in their own lives as academics and intellectuals (in part, state sponsored, as at the University of Illinois). And state agency needed to be acknowledged as a crucial ally and court of appeal, a means of realizing or consoli- dating progressive projects of social change, without which many calls for such change by Left academics risked sounding like empty posturing. This acknowledgment, they felt, was not hap- pening. The prevailing common sense they felt themselves to be pushing back against, whether explicitly anarchist or not, holds that appeals to the state are always fundamentally misguided. This common sense can be expressed by the titles of two recent books about the history of the 1930s: Götz Aly’s Hitler’s Beneficiaries: Plunder, Racial War, and the Nazi Welfare State and Wolf- 2 A full version of this argument is available in Bruce Robbins, Upward Mobility and the Common Good (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2007), chap. 5. 4 OCCASION gang Schivelbusch’s Three New Deals: Reflections of Roosevelt’s America, Mussolini’s Italy, and Hit- ler’s Germany, 1933–1939.3 In its critique of the welfare state, each book takes the highest possi- ble moral ground. Both tar the welfare state with the brush of fascism. Popular satisfaction with the militarism of the Third Reich was achieved in part, Aly argues, by a systematic distribution of plundered “foods, goods, and amenities” that must be described as “a kind of racist-totalitarian welfare state” (2). According to Schivelbusch, when Franklin Delano Roosevelt tried to establish a welfare state, he was drawn to imitate those that Mussolini and Hitler had already founded. In a 1933 review of Roosevelt’s Looking Forward, Mussolini himself praised the new American president’s agreement with the fascist principle “that the state no longer leaves the economy to its own devices, having recognized that the welfare of the economy is identical with the welfare of the people.”4 Exploring “points of convergence between Fascist Italy, Nazi Germany, and the deromanticized New Deal” (10), Schivelbusch proposes that even the militarism we find charac- teristic of Mussolini and Hitler goes deep into the historical roots of Roosevelt’s project as well. For Roosevelt, as for the Progressivism he learned from, “the words ‘welfare’ and ‘warfare’ soon became almost interchangeable” (47). For both, in short, orange juice literally does mean Agent Orange. In the United States since September 2001, it is both strange and not strange at all that this common sense should be so flourishing.5 It is strange because the big story of the late decades of the twentieth century, a story that has thus far extended its run effortlessly into the twenty-first, has of course been globalization. As far as the welfare state is concerned, this means the pressure of global capital and its champions at home to privatize, defund, and dismantle those few state institutions aimed at regulating the operation of the market in areas crucial to the general welfare and to protecting society’s most vulnerable members from the tender mercies of the bottom line. The strangeness of the refusal to defend or identify with such institutions can be multiplied by the number of American Foucaultians who, along with many ideas of greater value, also took over their master’s very French antistatism. The transnational parallel was always forced: there was clearly no equivalent on this side of the Atlantic to the centralized, panoptical French state to which Foucault’s antistatism was a philosophical rejoinder. And in the century’s final years, as I said, the timing was particularly bad. Americans were adopting this antistatism even as whole sections of the American state edifice were crashing down around them. When the government, urged by its corporate backers, repeatedly and systematically decimates the already thin ranks of those inspectors sent out to ensure the purity of our food, air, and water, it requires something of a leap of faith to believe inspection is the evil heart of the modern regime of power. And yet in another sense this belief is not strange at all. For the Bush administration’s re- sponse to the attacks of September 11th, 2001, was to institute a scale and intensity of surveil- lance that made even the least paranoid reach for their worn paperbacks of Nineteen Eighty-Four. The administration’s ideology might have been hostile to so-called big government, but the ef- fect was in the spirit of Big Brother. Along with the new military Keynesianism, anti-immigrant 3 Götz Aly, Hitler’s Beneficiaries: Plunder, Racial War, and the Nazi Welfare State, trans. Jefferson Chase (New York: Metropolitan Books, 2007). In German, the title is Hitlers Volksstaat (Hitler’s Welfare State). Wolfgang Schivelbusch, Three New Deals: Reflections of Roosevelt’s America, Mussolini’s Italy, and Hitler’s Germany, 1933–1939, trans. Jefferson Chase (New York: Metropolitan Books, 2006). 4 Quoted in Schivelbusch, Three New Deals, 23. 5 For an eloquent example of this common sense, see James C. Scott, Seeing Like a State: How Certain Schemes to Improve the Human Condition Have Failed (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1998). ROBBINS | ORANGE JUICE AND AGENT ORANGE 5 crackdowns and reinforcement of the borders, and the lawless augmentation of executive power, the systematic intrusiveness of the so-called War on Terror forced many of us to stop and ask ourselves whether the Foucaultians had not been right all along. Foucault had much else going for him. But the utter rejection of liberal reform with which he is rightly or wrongly associated could not have kept its hold over so many without serious help from the Bush government. Abu Ghraib, Guantánamo Bay, and the moral and legal horrors for which these place-names now stand have sustained this common sense. Nothing less dramatic could explain the sudden fash- ion for the Italian philosopher Giorgio Agamben. Agamben’s revolutionary messianism and his contempt for legal order and parliamentary politics, which were arguably nongeneralizable ef- fects of watching postwar Italy’s seamless transition from fascism to Christian Democracy, might seem another unlikely import to the United States in an era when the U.S. government has been acting in shameless defiance of human rights and international law.6 (Note that even under Obama, Guantánamo has not yet been shut down.) It seems clear that what the United States needs is more respect for democratic procedure, not less. Yet it is as if Bush’s disrespect for such procedures, his attempt to play the role of the charismatic leader who in a moment of national emergency rises above such petty norms, found a perversely sympathetic echo among many aca- demic humanists. Along with Agamben, they too seem to judge that the hollowness of liberal norms and institutions has been properly exposed, that we are long past the time when such norms and institutions could make any genuine appeal to our critical energies. With Agamben, they seem willing to take the extermination camp as the exemplary institution of the modern state, the deep truth not only of Nazism but of liberal governmentality as well. Whether critical thinkers in the humanities and cultural disciplines will prove supple enough to adapt to the Obama administration, which is to say to the possibility of a renewed discourse of state interven- tion and regulation in the interests of the American public at large, and even (such is the hope, at least) in the interests of the world outside America’s borders, is one of the more crucial ques- tions we are now facing. Theoretical common sense is always shaped by the impact of particular historical experi- ences. It generalizes more or less abusively, applying conclusions drawn from one experience to the urgencies of different places and institutional contexts. That is one challenge that I have tried to capture in the title “Orange Juice and Agent Orange.” What’s in a common color? Are we sure that the violence of the dioxin-bearing, cancer- and birth-defect-causing defoliant is the hidden truth behind the supplying to children of the humble citrus drink, rich in vitamin C? To return to Agamben and company: in addition to everything else they are, are the camps really exem- plary? One example calls up another. Consider the argument by James Ferguson and Akhil Gupta about the Anganwadi Program in India.7 Like the program that provided milk and orange juice to the young Carolyn Steedman, this one too was designed by the Indian government to provide better nutrition, in this case for pregnant women as well as young children in need. Dis- cussing this program’s surprise inspections, intended to ensure that local offices were actually carrying out this work, Ferguson and Gupta do not ask whether such inspections might be nec- essary and productive. Instead they dispute the state’s claim “to the general good,” to “national, as opposed to local, interest.” The thrust of the argument is a defense of the local and the par- ticular against the state’s claim “to represent the ‘greater’ good for the ‘larger’ dominion of the 6 Mark Mazower, “Foucault, Agamben: Theory and the Nazis,” boundary 2 35, no. 1 (2008): 23–34. 7 James Ferguson and Akhil Gupta, “Spatializing States: Toward an Ethnography of Neoliberal Governmentality,” American Ethnologist 29, no. 4 (2002): 981–1002. 6 OCCASION nation and the world” (988). To observers of modern India, the quotes around “greater” and “larger” may or may not seem self-evidently appropriate. But in the presence of arguments like this, which takes for granted that the local always needs to be supported at all costs against an in- trusive state whose claim to the general good is obviously bogus, an American may think back to the civil rights movement of the 1960s. There, as some will recall, the local was enthusiastically represented by Governor Orville Faubus and police chief Bull Connor. In Alabama and Missis- sippi, the defense of the local had a precise ideological content: racism. And the content of the federal government’s claim to represent the “national, as opposed to local, interest” was desegre- gation. Why are we so reluctant to believe that, like desegregation, better nutrition for pregnant women and young children in need might be a perfectly legitimate object of state policy, one that—given local resistance in both cases—might actually benefit from some oversight? If Bush’s detention camps were able to steal the show, distracting attention from other, very different instances of state intervention and from other institutions of surveillance, more horrify- ing to multinational corporations than to the world public at large, there is also a longer-term reason. This reason is the transnational turn in intellectual work, a strong preference for seeking coherence and significance in phenomena that transcend the nation-state and for subjecting na- tional phenomena to scrutiny in the name of planetary justice. Each of the editors, in her or his own way, has participated eagerly in this turn. None of us plans to forsake it. At a moment when some voices in the Obama administration are already hinting quietly that perhaps the economic crisis can be blamed on Chinese monetary policy, it would be foolhardy to assume that even the most ambitious “new New Deal”—something for which the chances are increasingly bleak— will manage to avoid making foreigners pay as much as possible of the price. Still, we have also tried to remain aware of the broader context and the dangers of political slippage that the trans- national perspective makes possible. Over the past thirty years, it has been global capital, as I noted above, that incited taxpayer revolt against institutions of government oversight and the call for their downsizing. In smoothing the intellectual passage to a generalized antistatism, en- thusiasts for the transnational have worked in unconscious and in many cases unwilling complic- ity with globalization. When intellectuals begin tracking cultural flows that cut across national borders, celebrating ever more complex forms of transnational hybridity, and so on, the assump- tion is too often that political sovereignty is either irrelevant or antagonistic to the critical enter- prise. What can a state do other than block flows of people, ideas, and cultures, stop them from mixing, arrest the process of aesthetic creation or identity creation? It can obviously detract, but what can a state possibly add to such objects of cultural interpretation? What sense does it make, then, to force literature and the welfare state together? The assumption here is that these questions are not merely rhetorical. Answers might be sought, for example, in some of the social categories with which the humanities in the United States have most intensely concerned themselves. One of the arguments made at the Illinois conference, and taken up again in this collection, is that it is not a coincidence that attacks on the welfare state should so often take on racist and misogynistic intonations. Women and people of color, often those most at risk in American society, have certainly been among the genuine bene- ficiaries of welfare programs. Among the many things the state has done in the United States is attempt, however reluctantly and unsatisfactorily, to diminish and embarrass racism in American society, or at least cushion against its lingering effects. A similar argument could be made about the state’s role in the women’s movement: the promulgating of laws protecting women from ROBBINS | ORANGE JUICE AND AGENT ORANGE 7 sexual harassment, and so on. When criticism takes up the categories of gender and race, it will leave out a lot if (to adapt a phrase from Theda Skocpol) it does not bring the state back in. But the title of my article tries to urge the reader toward a wider problematic. It asks about the connection between the state’s efforts at domestic amelioration, assuming such efforts are at least potentially substantive, and its actions at the international level. At the international level, it must be admitted, the picture changes immediately and drastically. Welfare, however modest, has by and large been restricted to people within the state’s borders. It is only within those bor- ders that the good has been recognized even very tentatively as common. The state’s treatment of those outside its borders has tended, on the contrary, to oscillate between the poles of indif- ference and violent aggression. The phrase “Agent Orange” keeps this aggression on display. It is arguable, though by no means firmly established, that the welfare state has managed to exist, in countries with more or less developed social services, only by taking advantage of the violence that the European powers in their colonial phase and the neocolonialism of the United States have been in the habit of meting out to countries that have no such services. It seems hard to deny that, historically speaking, funding for what were to become welfare institutions would have come at least in part from what can still be called imperialism. On the other hand, of what act of civilization would this well-documented dependence on barbarism not be true? How much can we properly deduce from it? No simple judgment seems adequate to this clash of equally valid perspectives. In a radio broadcast in 1946, looking back on what was admirable in the Victorian liberal- ism in which he was raised, E. M. Forster noted that liberalism’s sincere belief in social progress was achieved only by “exploiting the poor of our own country and the backward races abroad.”8 I think we would want to say now that liberalism’s limits, as Forster expresses them, number at least three: (1) its ill treatment of the poor at home, (2) its ill treatment of the “backward races” abroad, and (3) the fact that Forster, carrying on the tradition of liberalism, continues to use the phrase “backward races” without quotation marks. The question, however, is not how bad liber- alism’s history is, or even how far forward that history extends into today’s era of humanitarian intervention. The question is whether the tendency to disparage and mistreat non-Westerners is intrinsic to Western ideologies like liberalism and Marxism, which is to say whether liberalism and Marxism are intrinsically mismatched with Third World peoples. In his book Liberalism and Empire, the political theorist Uday Mehta suggests that they are indeed mismatched—that the failure of self-limitation indicated by numbers 2 and 3 is in fact constitutive of liberalism. “For the project of nineteenth-century liberalism . . . other peoples’ experience must be viewed as lack- ing coherence”9; other peoples must be viewed as objects requiring improvement. Liberalism, not in its antipathy to state interference but on the contrary in its positive vision of the state—in Lauren Goodlad’s words, “as a potential aid to individual and social welfare”10—is of course (along with pressure from below and from the Left) a major source of the welfare project. It is precisely this tradition that Mehta ties to imperialism abroad. “The stronger the claims for a par- ticular intervention being progressive, or bettering life, the more it has pressed against the exist- ing norms limiting the use of political power. And in that sense such claims have served to expand, and justify the expansion of, the domain of the political. . . . What is latent in the liberal 8 Simon Joyce, The Victorians in the Rearview Mirror (Columbus: Ohio State University Press, 2007), 43. 9 Uday Mehta, Liberalism and Empire (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999), 78–80, 212–13. 10 Lauren Goodlad, Victorian Literature and the Victorian State (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 2003), viii. 8 OCCASION conception of the political is a deep impulse to reform the world” (79). Marxism and liberalism share “a view of the world as something malleable through political effort” (80). If this view of the world was contained and contested at home, in the empire it takes over. “In the Empire, this . . . urge to reform and progress . . . becomes virtually determinative” (80). The welfare state side of liberalism is conceptually aligned with its imperialist side: both are interventionist. The liberal justification of empire is the imperative, to which liberalism fixes no limits, to intervene and im- prove. Mehta invites us therefore to try a thought experiment: to imagine the world as not need- ing political improvement. From this experimental viewpoint Edmund Burke, a conservative who resisted schemes of improvement that intruded upon the givenness of custom and locality and thus spent his best energies fighting the East India Company, becomes Mehta’s antiliberal hero, a planetary pro- gressive precisely because he was not a domestic one. In the context of today’s human rights militarism, this impulse to reverse the meanings of Left and Right at the international scale is ever more understandable. And yet on reflection, something more complex than a reversal seems called for. What happens in South Asia once the pre-1947 division of colonizer and colo- nized no longer suffices to guide political demands and identities—as I think it no longer does suffice? Is Burke still a model to emulate, a figure of the proper Left, within India? Could any In- dian citizen, naturally concerned about flagrant inequalities and systemic injustices of various sorts, rest content with the thought experiment of imagining Indian society as in need of no im- provement other than at the individual, ethical scale? To ask this question is, I think, to answer it. We are speaking of a country where despite impressive economic growth at least half the population, or something like five or six hundred million people, currently live below the poverty line set by the Indian government itself, which is to say below an income of approximately two hundred dollars per year. In such a situation—and India’s is superior in this sense to many oth- ers—to adopt Mehta’s thought experiment and consider the social world as needing only indi- vidual ethical improvement seems to me an unspeakable obscenity. If you fix your eyes on the five or six or seven hundred million people living in severe and life-threatening deprivation, talk of the sacred givenness of place and custom can only sound like what it clearly was for Burke: a defense of the status quo, which is to say a defense of the comforts and privileges of a ruling elite at the expense of most of humanity. This would be the moment, mimicking what Burke did at the trial of Warren Hastings, to tell atrocity stories about deprivation and injustice that, like some of Carolyn Steedman’s, make it almost impossible to sit still. I ask the reader to take it on faith that I could tell such stories and that they would inform us that yes, pace Mehta, the world does after all need improving, drastic improving, political improving. We know that atrocity stories are often used to make listeners forget what agent is being invited to intervene, how much that agent has to answer for, how tainted its motives are, and so on. None of these can be safely forgotten. An ethical language must be found that recognizes the need for restraint of arrogant and self-authorized intervention by those who have the power to intervene, like the United States. The right to intervene cannot be restricted to the powerful. Still, that self-limiting language will also have to posit the need for intervention and the need for improvement. It cannot discount the state as one agent of im- provement. And when it thinks about improvement, it will have to borrow some of the state’s own abstractness. Consider an example of outrage expressed in dry statistical form, statistics be- ing the characteristic language of the state. The utilitarian philosopher Ted Honderich has calcu- lated that on September 11, 2001, “when 3000 were killed at the Twin Towers and the Pentagon ROBBINS | ORANGE JUICE AND AGENT ORANGE 9 . . . on that day, if deaths by starvation for 2001 were spread evenly throughout the year, 23,000 people died of hunger.”11 It is only the bureaucratic impersonality of this language, learned from the state and then extended beyond it, that permits us to define injustice properly and thus even to conceive of doing something about it. The issue of how to relate larger and smaller ethical scales has a long, if somewhat obscure, history. The disparity between the two is already striking in Thomas More’s Utopia, where out- side its borders the ideal commonwealth does not obey the same principles it subscribes to within them. The development of international law, both late and eccentric in its relation to or- dinary state-centric law, offers much to reflect on from this perspective. Today the eccentricity question is suddenly central to debates in postcolonial studies. Postcolonial critics can no longer count on the simple and professionally convenient faith that the existence of empire must have expressed itself at the center of metropolitan culture and must therefore lie there awaiting schol- arly exposure. Perhaps, as the interviewers of Politics and Letters once suggested to Raymond Williams apropos of the Irish Famine and the realist novels of the 1840s, even the most apoca- lyptic results of imperialism did not show up in even the most sensitive instances of the domestic “structure of feeling.” If not, there would be a good side as well as a bad side to the disconnect—for evidence of the relative autonomy of the national would make it a bit harder to disqualify every claim to pro- gressive achievement in the domestic sphere by means of a crushing reference to visible foreign crimes. It was a few such achievements that E. P. Thompson listed in his rejoinder to Perry An- derson, who had judged the English working-class movement by the extremely demanding crite- rion of unmade revolution and thus found it wanting. “The abolition of factory labor for children under the age of 11, or the institution of divorce, or the penny-post, may affect the power-model [i.e., revolution] scarcely at all; but for those who were then living these may have affected them inexpressibly or quite perceptibly.”12 His opponents, Thompson said, see “social reforms” merely “as distractions from ‘hegemonic’ aspirations. . . . But surely any mature view of history (or of contemporary actuality) must in some way combine evaluations of both kinds” (87)—in other words, both ultimate goals and immediate changes in “the quality of life,” in particular those provisionally enforced by state action. As the university’s least practical branch, the humanities have tended to feel most at home when speaking in the name of ultimate goals and ultimate values. Discomfort with apparent im- provements in the day-to-day quality of life, with reform in general, and with the utilitarian re- former Jeremy Bentham in particular forms an intriguing constant from Matthew Arnold to Michel Foucault. Yet Arnold was of course an educational reformer, and Foucault spoke very eloquently in defense of Social Security. Things were not better, he reminded us, when old peo- ple were tucked away for prolonged periods in the family’s attic. It is not clear that critics in ei- ther the Arnold or the Foucault lineage—arguably the same lineage, with minor inflections—are entirely on the same page as their discursive forefathers when they scorn less-than-apocalyptic improvement and neglect the daily functioning of the institutions that educate the young, pro- tect the old, or step in when the status of temporarily able-bodied is suddenly withdrawn and someone neither young nor old is pushed into sharing their common dependence and vulner- ability. It is also unclear whether we critics have the right to make that grandiose claim to public 11 Ted Honderich, Terrorism for Humanity: Inquiries in Political Philosophy (London: Pluto, 2003), 23–24. 12 E. P. Thompson, “The Peculiarities of the English” (1965), in The Poverty of Theory and Other Essays (London: Merlin Press, 1978), 86–87. 10 OCCASION significance disguised by allusions to “politics” if all our interpretive commitments are pegged to the ultimate, a safely postponed realm where dilemmas, alliances, and dirty hands—usually thought to be the stuff of politics—do not have to be confronted. Hence our project: to elicit a conversation with various positions in and around the humanities that assume, not without provocation, that the ultimate malevolence of the state is a safe guide to political judgment. The issue here cannot be resolved by anything so simple as a choice between short term and long term, reform and revolution, justice at the level of the nation and justice at the level of the planet. We are obliged to live these different scales and goals and temporal rhythms simultane- ously, yet without any guarantee that they can be made to conform to each other. This means that we must get used to a schizophrenic politics. We must live with and within the contradiction of struggling at home to increase national solidarity, to raise national solidarity to the level necessary for the defense of welfare institutions (even though those institutions will not help the much need- ier people who are neither citizens nor residents of the United States), while working to detach Americans from the sorts of national solidarity that permit chauvinist adventures like the current war in Iraq. And we must struggle at the global level to see that non-Americans are provided with (or get to keep) the welfare institutions that they need or that global capital (with our help) is vig- orously trying to undermine. The global struggle is of course already going on. There are at least glimmers of coherence between global and domestic. If you look deeper into recent election results in the Middle East, the success of what looks to some like extremism might seem better described as a demand for social welfare at all costs. As Saba Mahmood writes in The Politics of Piety, “Islamic welfare organizations around the Muslim world have increasingly stepped in to fill the vacuum left by post-colonial states as these states, under neoliberal economic pressures, have withdrawn from providing social services to their citizens.”13 I would argue that the generalizing of the welfare state is already the unstated goal of much of the world’s “antiglobalization” or rather counterglobaliza- tion movement, which demands regulation in place of free-market chaos. From the perspective of politics, then, the question is whether people like ourselves are ready to join these struggles without the comforts of full and prepaid consistency. From the perspective of literature, the word “struggles” might seem an example of egre- gious overreaching. Literature participates in the life of its time without, for the most part, taking an active part in its decisive battles. Nor does it necessarily have much to say about the state. Po- ets have worked in customs houses and consulates, but that is not by and large what they wrote poems about. The state is of course the object of those struggles that we most readily name “po- litical,” as in Shakespeare’s history plays, but the sort of modern state action suggested by “wel- fare” does not always rate even that adjective. To say that neither the state in general nor welfare in particular has a prominent place in modern literature would be something of an understate- ment. In the nineteenth century, when the modern state bureaucracy was taking shape, the novel offers little more than occasional glimpses into the workhouse, the schoolhouse, the orphanage, the courts, and above all the police.14 Aside from some plague stories from Defoe to Camus, passing through Bleak House and Middlemarch, it is hard to think of interesting creative attention 13 Saba Mahmood, The Politics of Piety (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2005), xi. 14 “The neo-conservative return to the Victorians was inseparable from contemporary efforts to reform the welfare state” (Joyce, Victorians in the Rearview Mirror, 145). Defense against the modernist anti-Victorian contempt concedes something to Himmelfarb: “what was increasingly enshrined in the second half of the nineteenth century was the idea of an impersonal and bureaucratic state as the only available option for dealing with large-scale social problems, especially when the alternative options were private charity and a philanthropic moralism” (146).

Description:
Dec 20, 2010 Don DeLillo, Underworld. THE PHRASE FROM DON DELILLO THAT I HAVE TAKEN AS MY TITLE spontaneously re-created itself at the
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.