ebook img

Hypotheses and Perspectives in the History and Philosophy of Science: Homage to Alexandre Koyré, 1892–1964 PDF

497 Pages·2017·7.226 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Hypotheses and Perspectives in the History and Philosophy of Science: Homage to Alexandre Koyré, 1892–1964

Raff aele Pisano Joseph Agassi Daria Drozdova Editors Hypotheses and Perspectives in the History and Philosophy of Science Homage to Alexandre Koyré 1892-1964 Hypotheses and Perspectives in the History and Philosophy of Science Raffaele Pisano • Joseph Agassi Daria Drozdova Editors Hypotheses and Perspectives in the History and Philosophy of Science Homage to Alexandre Koyré 1892-1964 Editors Raffaele Pisano Joseph Agassi Lille University Tel Aviv University Villeneuve d’Ascq, France Tel Aviv, Israel Daria Drozdova National Research University Higher School of Economics Moscow, Russian Federation ISBN 978-3-319-61710-7 ISBN 978-3-319-61712-1 (eBook) DOI 10.1007/978-3-319-61712-1 Library of Congress Control Number: 2017952599 © Springer International Publishing AG 2018 This work is subject to copyright. All rights are reserved by the Publisher, whether the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed. The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use. The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or the editors give a warranty, express or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations. Printed on acid-free paper This Springer imprint is published by Springer Nature The registered company is Springer International Publishing AG The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland Foreword A Scholar Without Borders Like Einstein, Alexandre Koyré could have thought of himself as a citizen of the world.1 He was one of those scholars who went through the turmoil of two world wars clearly aware of their civic allegiance and deeply concerned about the future of civilization, without ever endorsing nationalistic claims. Born in tsarist Russia in the early years of the oil boom in Baku, Koyré took his secondary education in present-day Georgia and went to Göttingen University in 1908 (Zambelli 2016). Three years later, he moved on to Paris, where he started his PhD research at the École Pratique des Hautes Études. In 1914, although he was still a foreigner in France, he first enlisted in the French army and then soon volunteered to fight in a Russian regiment. However, during the October 1917 Revolution, he did not join any of the rival movements and came back to Paris. Koyré never really settled in France, although he got a number of teaching posi- tions and became a French citizen.2 He traveled all over Europe, in the Middle East, in Argentina, and in the United States. In 1940, during the German invasion of France, he was lecturing in Cairo. He quickly decided to rally the Free French Troops, and de Gaulle sent him to the United States. After a long journey via India, the Pacific Ocean, and San Francisco, the Koyrés arrived in New York. There, Alexandre joined the New School of Social Research and became dean of the École Libre des Hautes Études, a consortium of Belgian and French scholars in exile (Gillispie 2008). Koyré could feel at ease everywhere, but he really belonged to nowhere. As he was fluent in many languages – at least Russian, German, French, and English – he could study and teach in many countries, including France, Egypt, Lebanon, and the 1 Einstein is famous for this humorous remark in his address to the French Philosophical Society at the Sorbonne (6 April 1922): “If my theory of relativity is proven successful, Germany will claim me as a German and France will declare that I am a citizen of the world. Should my theory prove untrue, France will say that I am a German and Germany will declare that I am a Jew” (French press clipping, 7 April 1922 [Einstein Archive 36–378], and Berliner Tageblatt, 8 April 1922 [Einstein Archive 79–535]). 2 It seems that he got the French citizenship on November 23, 1922, thanks to a decree of “admis- sion at home” which had to be renewed every five year. v vi Foreword United States. Thanks to his good command of classical Latin, he could also immerse himself in medieval and Renaissance studies. He developed such a remark- able intellectual flexibility that he could read and empathically interpret early mod- ern mystics (Koyré 1929), as well as Descartes’ metaphysics, Galileo’s physics, and Newton’s dynamics. Among his students and collaborators, he was famous for his sharp understanding of subtle nuances in text analysis and translation (Koyré 1943; Cohen 1987). Across Disciplinary Boundaries Although at the turn of the twentieth century a disciplinary organization came to prevail in academic research, Koyré never fully embraced a disciplinary identity. For example, he studied philosophy under Edmund Husserl in Göttingen, but, what- ever the deep influence the founder of phenomenology had upon him, he was not brainwashed by his first mentor, nor was he converted to the then-booming field of axiomatization of mathematics by David Hilbert’s lectures in Göttingen. When he completed his philosophical training in Paris, he attended Henri Bergson’s lectures at the Collège de France, which attracted crowds of the Parisian intellectual elite (Azouvi 2007). He also attended the Sorbonne courses of André Lalande and Emile Brunschvicg, two of the leading figures of the Société Française de Philosophie. Yet Koyré was not really attracted by mainstream and star philosophers. Rather, he became a disciple of a more marginal philosopher of science, Emile Meyerson, who was an immigrant in France, like himself. Meyerson, who was already in his sixties, invited Koyré and his wife Dora to his home and even occasionally supported them financially when Alexandre was jobless. Until Meyerson’s death in 1933, Koyré used to call him “mon cher maître” and visited him every Thursday in his salon (Meyerson 2009, pp. 226–253). More surprisingly, Koyré did not dedicate his earlier scholarship to the history or the philosophy of science. He was primarily interested in early modern religious thought and theology. Following his PhD on St. Anselm, he moved on to Descartes’ proof of the existence of God (Koyré 1922, 1923). He got a temporary lectureship in history of religious thought at the École Pratique. When it was turned into a ten- ured position of directeur d’études in 1932, Koyré lectured about the relations between science and faith. He did not give up the history of philosophy, for that matter. In 1929, as he was appointed lecturer in philosophy at Montpellier University, he tried to introduce his students (“mes gosses” as he referred to them) to Hegel’s system. He subsequently wrote a state-of-the-art report and an introduction to Hegel’s doctrine. At the same time, he diligently paid tribute to his mentors, editing Husserl’s Recherches Philosophiques and dedicating reviews and articles to Meyerson in various languages (Koyré 1926, 1927, 1931, 1933). Indeed, this was a characteristic feature of Koyré’s career: while he was building up his own philo- sophical framework, he was keen to spread the views of the thinkers who mattered for him. Sharing knowledge was his priority. He also studied Russian intellectual Foreword vii history for a course at the Institute of Slavic Studies of the University of Paris and published two major volumes on this topic (Koyré 1929, 1950). Given the variety of domains of expertise that Koyré displayed in his career, how are we to understand that he is mainly considered as a historian of science? Galileo and Koyré In 1941, Koyré arrived in the United States with the three volumes of his Etudes Galiléennes in his suitcase (Koyré 1939). The book, recently published in Paris, provided the basis of his courses in New York and Cambridge in 1942–1943. The history of science, as it developed in the United States in the interwar period under the influence of George Sarton, the founder of Isis, was seen above all as a chrono- logical series of descriptions of discoveries, carefully detached from their social and intellectual contexts. Arnold Thackeray later characterized this early period of insti- tutionalization of the history of science in the United States as the prehistory (Thackray 1980). Against this background, Koyré’s lectures on Galileo created a great impression on a dozen scholars. Isaac Bernard Cohen, among them, was immediately attracted by Koyré’s approach to the history of science. What Koyré offered was nothing like a boring linear chronology of great discoveries supposedly made due to crucial experiments. Koyré’s attempt to analyze Galileo’s thinking pro- cess and to outline the inner coherence of his system revealed an exciting battle of ideas about natural phenomena. “From Koyré we learned about the inner dynamic quality of scientific thought” (Cohen 1987, p. 56). It is fair to say that Koyré invented a new Galileo, a Platonist Galileo who, in turn, invented Koyré as a post-positivist historian of modern science. Not all students were convinced by Koyré’s portrait of Galileo. Giorgio de Santillana and Leonardo Olschki could not agree that Galileo did not actually per- form the experiments that he presented. In addition, they raised objections. Still, the long controversy that ensued with Olschki and later with Stillman Drake enhanced the aura surrounding Koyré in the United States. Unlike other French refugees, Koyré did not leave his country of exile in the aftermath of World War II. Indeed, he came back to Paris to resume his position at the École Pratique and his lectures on religious thought, but he shared his time between the United States and Paris. In 1951–1952, he was elected a fellow at the Institute for Advanced Studies in Princeton, and he spent half of the years there. But he did not stay quietly in Princeton when he was in the United States. Always on the move, Koyré lectured in Chicago, at Johns Hopkins in Baltimore, and at the University of Wisconsin in Madison, thus attracting an increasing number of young scholars at a crucial moment when history of science was being promoted as a profession in the US university system (Aurières 2017). Koyré’s intellectual approach to science, emphasizing the unity of thought through the close interaction between science, religion, and metaphysics, was par- ticularly attractive in the heyday of the Cold War. It potentially provided US histo- viii Foreword rians of science with a robust armor against the increasing influence of the Marxist interpretations of history of science, such as that developed in Britain by John D. Bernal and his followers. Koyré’s intellectual history was a good antidote for addressing what was identified as perhaps the most “critical problem” in the field – the intense philosophical debate about the impact of economic and social structures on scientific change. This question pervaded the Conference on the History of Science held in Madison in 1957, the year of Sputnik, and was reflected in the resulting widely read volume edited by Marshall Clagett (Clagett 1959; Fuller 2000). Through its widespread circulation in the right places at the right moment, the Etudes Galiléennes became a landmark book, one of those books which opened up new research pathways for decades. In a minor key, Koyré’s Études Galiléennes anticipated the later grand impact of Thomas Kuhn’s Structure of Scientific Revolutions. In this volume, published 2 years before Koyré’s death, Kuhn acknowl- edged Koyré’s influence on his vision of scientific change (Kuhn 1962, p. v–vi, 1977, p. 11; Conant and Haugeland, pp. 286). Ambiguous Heritage in France The contrast between the impact of Koyré’s works in the United States and in France is striking. While he influenced an entire generation of historians of science and thus greatly contributed to professionalizing and dignifying the history of science in American universities, in France, his courses at the École Pratique des Hautes Études attracted few students. I.B. Cohen, in keeping with a remark by Gillispie, contrasted the image of Koyré as a historian of science in the United States with his reputation as a philosopher in Europe (Cohen 1987, p. 64). However, this is not exactly the case, since Koyré has never been recognized as a philosopher in France and his sphere of influence there in the history of science remained more limited than in the United States. In the 1950s, when the Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique was estab- lished, history of science was integrated into the philosophy section, and Koyré was part of it. The coupling of philosophy and history of science is a major feature of the French system and has long favored the practice of intellectual history focused on scientific concepts and ideas. Yet Koyré did not benefit from this situation. To be sure, the students he recruited at the École Pratique gradually assisted him and later became professional historians of science or technology (Taton 1987). But Koyré was rebuffed in 1951, when he applied for a position at the Collège de France, just as Meyerson had been turned down 30 years before. Both of them remained at the periphery of the French system, because they did not follow the standard cursus of French academics (Chimisso 2008). Moreover, Koyré’s program of a history of scientific ideas was rivaled by the overarching influence of Gaston Bachelard’s historical epistemology. Well estab- lished at the Centre of History of Science and Technology of the Sorbonne, Foreword ix Bachelard attracted large audiences and created a research school of philosophers cum historians of science, including Georges Canguilhem. In 1958, an alternative Centre of History of Science and Technology was created for Koyré by the École Pratique des Hautes Études, which in 1966 was rechristened the Centre Alexandre Koyré. For decades, there were virtually no interactions between the two centers respectively located on the left bank and the right bank of the river Seine. Canguilhem nevertheless later boldly claimed that Koyré was part of the “French tradition of epistemology,” on the assumption that Koyré’s interpretation of the scientific revo- lution exemplified Bachelard’s “epistemology of rupture” (Canguilhem 1968, p. 14). Although this view distorts Koyré’s much more sophisticated history of ideas, it has been widely spread and has become a kind of golden legend among French epistemologists (Bensaude-Vincent 2016). Still, the golden legend about the “French tradition of epistemology” hardly conceals the cleavage between two rival traditions of history of science and the subsequent marginalization of Koyré. Remarkably, it was an Italian scholar, Pietro Redondi, member of the Centre Alexandre Koyré, who edited the volume of Koyré’s lectures (Redondi 1986). The time has come to reconsider Koyré’s works in a broad international perspec- tive and the present volume will hopefully pave the way for a reassessment of his influence. CETCOPRA, Université Paris 1 Bernadette Bensaude-Vincent Panthéon Sorbonne Paris, France [email protected] References Aurières E (2017) Alexandre Koyré aux Etats-Unis: un ambassadeur de l’histoire des sciences, PhD. Diss., Université Paris 1 Panthéon-Sorbonne. Azouvi F (2007) La gloire de Bergson. Essai sur le magistère philosophique. Gallimard, Paris. Bensaude-Vincent B (2016) Koyré dans la légende dorée de la tradition épistémologique française, Communication delivered at the conference Actualité d’Alexandre Koyré. October 18. Centre Alexandre Koyré, Paris. Canguilhem G (1968) Introduction : l’objet de l’histoire des sciences in Études d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences concernant les vivants et la vie. Vrin, Paris. Chimisso C (2008) Writing the History of the Mind: Philosophy and Science in France, 1900 to 1960s. The Open University, Milton Keynes–UK. Clagett M (1959) (ed) Critical problems in the History of Science. The University of Wisconsin Press, Madison Cohen IB (1987) Alexandre Koyré in America: some personal reminiscences. History and Technology: An International Journal 4/1–4:55–70. Conant J, Haugeland J (2000) (eds) The Road Since Structure. Thomas S. Kuhn. Philosophical Essays, 1970-1993, with an Autobiographical Interview. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Fuller S (2000) Thomas Kuhn, A Philosophical History for Our Times. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago. x Foreword Gillispie CG (2008) Entry: Alexandre Koyré. Complete Dictionary of Scientific Biography. Retrieved January 2017 http://www.encyclopedia.com/doc/1G2–2830902380.html the web- link does not work Koyré A (1922) Essai sur I’idée de Dieu et les preuves de son existence chez Descartes. Ernest Leroux, Paris. Koyré A (1923) L’idée de Dieu dans la philosophie de St. Anselme. Ernest Leroux, Paris. Koyré A (1926) La tragédie de la raison. La philosophie de Émile Meyerson [in Russian]. Zveno 2–4 and 11–12. Koyré A (1927) É. Meyerson. La déduction relativiste [in Russian]. Versty 2:269–274. Koyré A (1929 [1979]) La philosophie de Jacob Boehme. Étude sur les origines de la métaphy- sique allemande. 3rd édition. Vrin, Paris. Koyré A (1929 [1976]) La philosophie et le problème national en Russie au début du XIXe s., Librairie Honoré Champion, Paris. 2nd édition. Gallimard, Paris. Koyré A (1931) Die Philosophie Émile Meyerson. Deutsch–Französische Rundschau 4:197–217. Koyré A (1933) Du cheminement de la pensée, par É. Meyerson. Journal de psychologie normale et pathologique 27:647–655. Koyré A (1939) Études galiléennes. Vol. I. À l’aube de la science classique. Vol. II La loi de la chute des corps. Descartes et Galilée, Vol. III Galilée et la loi d’inertie. Hermann, Paris. [Reprint 1966 and 1980] Koyré A (1943) Traddutore–tradittore, à propos de Copernic et de Galilée. Isis, 34/95 [1966. reprinted in Études d’histoire de la pensée scientifique. Gallimard, Paris, pp. 272–274. Koyré A (1950) Études sur l’histoire de la pensée philosophique en Russie, Vrin, Paris. Kuhn T (1962 [1970]) The Structure of Scientific Revolution. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago. 2nd ed. [see also Id. (1977) The Essential Tension, The University of Chicago Press, Chicago. Meyerson E (2009) Lettres françaises, edited by B. Bensaude-Vincent and E. Telkes–Klein. CNRS éditions, Paris. Redondi P (1986) (ed) Alexandre Koyré. De la mystique à la science. Cours et conférences (1922– 1962) [2nd ed. 2016]. EHESS, Paris Taton R (1987) Alexandre Koyré et l’essor de l’histoire des sciences en France (1933 à 1964). History & Technology 4/1–4:37–53. Thackray A (1980) The Pre–History of an Academic Discipline: The Study of the History of Science in the United States, 1891–1941. Minerva 18:448–473. Zambelli P (2016) Alexandre Koyré in incognito. Olschki, Paris.

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.