ebook img

Applications of Abduction: Knowledge-level Modelling PDF

31 Pages·2010·0.42 MB·English
by  MenziesT.
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Applications of Abduction: Knowledge-level Modelling

Int . J . Human – Computer Studies (1996) 45 , 305 – 335 Applications of abduction: knowledge-level modelling T I M M E N Z I E S † Department of Software De ! elopment , Monash Uni ! ersity , Caulfield East , Melbourne , Australia , 3 1 8 5 email : timm ê insect .sd .monash .edu .au ( Recei ! ed 5 September 1 9 9 5 and accepted in re ! ised form 2 5 March 1 9 9 6 ) A single inference procedure (abduction) can operationalise a wide variety of knowledge-level modelling problem solving methods ; i . e . prediction , classification , explanation , tutoring , qualitative reasoning , planning , monitoring , set-covering diagnosis , consistency-based diagnosis , validation , and verification . This abductive approach of fers a uniform view of dif ferent problem solving methods in the style proposed by Clancey and Breuker . Also , this adbuctive approach is easily extensible to validation ; i . e . using this technique we can implement both inference tools and testing tools . Further , abduction can execute in vague and conflicting domains (which we believe occur very frequently) . We therefore propose abduction as a framework for knowledge-level modelling . ÷ 1996 Academic Press Limited 1 . Introduction In the 1970s and early 1980s , several high-profile expert system successes were documented : e . g . MYCIN (Yu et al . , 1979) , CASNET (Weiss , Kulikowski & Amarel , 1978) , PROSPECTOR (Campbell , Hoilister , Duda & Hart , 1982 ; Duda , Hart & Reboh , 1985) and XCON (Bachant & McDermott , 1984) . However , despite careful attempts to generalize this work (e . g . Stefik et al . , 1982) , expert systems construction remains a somewhat hit-and-miss process . By the end of the 1980s , it was recognized that our design concepts for knowledge-based systems were incomplete (Buchanan & Smith , 1989) . A new expert system design approach (which has come to dominate the knowledge acquisition field) is the search for reusable abstract domain-independent problem-solving strategies . We call this approach KL since it is a variant of B Newell’s knowledge le ! el (KL) modelling approach (Newell , 1982 , 1993 ; Newell , Yost , Laird , Rosenbloom & Altmann , 1991 ; Menzies , 1995) . The fundamental premise of KL is that a knowledge base should be divided into domain-specific B facts and domain-independent abstract problem solving inference procedures [e . g . Clancey’s (1992) model construction operators , Steels’ (1990) components of expertise , Chandrasekaran’s task analysis , SPARK / BURN / FIREFIGHTER (Marques , Dallemagne , Kliner , McDermott & Tung , 1992) and KADS (Wielinga , Schreiber & Breuker , 1992)] . KL refers to Newell’s research on the knowledge A † Past papers available from http : / / www . sd . monash . edu . au / ! timm / pub / docs / papersonly . html . 305 1071-5819 / 96 / 090305 " 31$18 . 00 / 0 ÷ 1996 Academic Press Limited 306 T . MENZIES level (Newell , 1982 , 1993 ; Newell et al . , 1991) and the SOAR project (Yost & Newell , 1989 ; Rosenbloom , Laird & Newell , 1993) . KL does not explicitly model A problem-solving procedures . The observation that a KL system such as SOAR is A performing classification is a user-interpretation of the following . (1) The application of domain-specific knowledge controlling . . . (2) . . . a single inference procedure (operator selection over a problem space traversal) (Yost & Newell , 1989) . This paper argues for a variant on the KL approach . Like KL , we will use a A A single inference procedure (abduction) . However , we take a graph-theoretic approach rather than the production-system approach used by SOAR (see Section 6 . 2 . for a comparision of our approach and SOAR) . We find that a wide-variety of problem solving strategies are merely dif ferent types of calls to the same abduction procedure . Such uniformity simplifies the construction of interfaces between the inputs and outputs of dif ferent problem solving types . Breuker argues that such interfacing is essential since most problem solving types are used in combination to perform some task (Breuker , 1994) . Far from being a radical proposal , we find that our abductive process directly operationalizes the theory subset extraction process that Breuker (1994) and Clancey (1985 , 1992) argue is at the core of expert systems . Clancey of fers a two-layered extraction process (qualitative model to situation-specific model) while Breuker of fers a four-layered view (generic domain model to case model to conclusion to argument structure) . We take theory subset extraction to be a literal description of the internals of expert systems inference . Our research goal is the description of the minimal architecture necessary to perform this process . This paper is organized as follows . A summary of the terms introduced in this article is given in Figure 1 . Section 2 describes the theory subset extraction described by Clancey and Breuker . Section 3 describes our abducti ! e framework . Section 4 discusses the use of abduction for a variety of KL tasks ; i . e . prediction , B classification , explanation , tutoring , qualitative reasoning , planning , monitoring , set-covering diagnosis , consistency-based diagnosis , validation , and verification . Section 5 discusses the practicality of our proposal . Section 6 discusses some related work and issues . Note that this work is part of our abducti ! e reasoning project . We believe that abduction provides a comprehensive picture of declarative knowledge-based systems (KBS) inference . Apart from the problem solving methods discussed here , we also believe that abduction is a useful framework for intelligent decision support systems (Menzies , 1995 a ) , diagrammatic reasoning (Menzies & Compton , 1994) , single-user knowledge acquisition , and multiple-expert knowledge acquisition (Menzies , 1995 c ) . Further , abduction could model certain interesting features of human cognition (Menzies , 1995 d ) . Others argue elsewhere that abduction is also a framework for natural-language processing (Ng & Mooney) , design (Poole , 1990 a ) , visual pattern recognition (Poole , 1990 b ) , analogical reasoning (Falkenhainer , 1990) , financial reasoning (Hamscher , 1990) , machine learning (Hirata , 1994) and case-based reasoning (Leake , 1993) . APPLICATIONS OF ABDUCTION : KNOWLEDGE-LEVEL MODELLING 307 " X" , X ! Y Size of the set X , the intersection of the sets X and Y S A statement provided by an expert . T A theory comprising a set of statements ; e . g . Figures 2 and 9 . D A dependency graph showing connections between literals in T ; e . g . Figures 3 and 10 . # V , E $ Vertices and edges in D . Vertices are either and-vertices V and or or-vertices V o r . I An invariants predicate reporting pairs of incompatible vertices in D . NOGOODS Sets of incompatible vertices ; generated using I . model compiler A translator from T to D . F The fanout of D ; i . e . average number of edges from a vertex . " E" F # . " V" OUT The subset of V we are trying to explain . IN The subset of V which are acceptable starting-points of an explantion . FACTS Vertices we cannot doubt . DEFAULTS IN vertices that are not FACTS . P Proof trees connecting OUT to IN . Each proof P using vertices i V used , and avoids the vertices V forbid . i i A Assumptions made by P ; i . e . P used $ FACTS . i A Assumptions which I tells us are contradictory . C A The most upstream controversial assumptions . B ENV Maximal (with respect to size) consistent (defined using I ) subsets of A . B W A world : the set of proofs that are consistent with ENV ; e . g . i i Figures 4 and 5 . co ! er , causes Outputs and inputs in a world . co ! er # " OUT ! W i " ; causes # " IN ! W i " . BEST Competing worlds are judged by the BEST assessment operator . TASK The goal of an inference procedure : TASK # # BEST , IN , OUT $ . F IGURE 1 . Summary of terms . 2 . Clancey & Breuker In this section , we argue that the common theme between Clancey’s and Breuker’s view of expert systems inference is the extraction of sub-theory from a super-theory . 2 . 1 . MODEL CONSTRUCTION OPERATORS Clancey characterizes expert system inference as model construction operators that create a situation - specific model (SSM) from a general qualitati ! e model (QM) in the knowledge base (KB) . Clancey’s QM is like a first-order theory whose relations model causality , sub-types , and temporal relations . At runtime , portions of this 308 T . MENZIES theory are accessed and the variables are bound . This ground subset of the full theory is the SSM ; i . e . ‘‘the specific model the program is constructing of the particular system it is (processing)’’ (Clancey , 1992) . This specific model is the subset of the QM that is relevant to the task at hand . Clancey argues that there are two basic problem-solving methods used by expert systems : heuristic classification and heuristic construction (Clancey , 1992) . By heuristic classification , Clancey means that the inference engine merely selects a pre-existing inference path . In heuristic classification , this pathway would include the following . $ Inference to an abstracted description of the problem at hand . $ A partial match of this problem to an abstracted solution . $ An inference that specialises the abstracted solution to a solution relevant to the current problem . By heuristic construction , Clancey means that the inference engine constructs its conclusions from partial inferences supplied in the knowledge base . Construction is much harder than mere selection . Literals in dif ferent partial proofs may be mutually exclusive ; i . e . while we can believe A ∨ B , it may not be true that we can believe A ∧ B . The constructed SSM must be built with care in order to take into account these cancelation interactions . Multiple , mutually exclusive , SSMs may be possible and these must be mamaged separately . Extra architecture is required to handle conflicts and dependencies within the SSM . 2 . 2 . COMPONENTS OF SOLUTIONS Breuker explores the relationships between problem solving techniques used in expert systems (i . e . modelling , planning , design , assignment , prediction , assessment , monitoring and diagnosis) (Breuker , 1994) . He of fers an abstract description of the ‘‘components of a solution’’ generated by these techniques which , he argues , are of four types . $ A case model (equivalent to Clancey’s SSM) that represents some understand- ing of a problem . $ A conclusion , which is some answer to a question posed by the problem definition . $ An argument structure , which is supporting evidence for the conclusion generated . $ The case model which is generated from some generic domain model (equivalent to Clancey’s QM) . An argument structure is extracted from the case model . The conclusion is the portion of an argument structure that is relevant to the user . In the case where all the solution components are represented as a ground propositional theory whose APPLICATIONS OF ABDUCTION : KNOWLEDGE-LEVEL MODELLING 309 ++ x y ++ ++ ++ d ++ a ++ e c ++ g ++ –– ++ b f –– F IGURE 2 . An indeterminate qualitative theory . dependency graph has edges E , then : edges ( answer ) ‘ edges ( argument structure ) ‘ edges ( case model ) ‘ ( edges ( generic domain model ) # E ) where edges ( X ) denotes the edges of the dependency graph present in X . 2 . 3 . THEORY SUBSET EXTRACTION : AN EXAMPLE We now describe theory subset extraction in detail using a theory of vertices V and edges E . This example will informally introduce many of the concepts we will return to later . In summary , we will search our theory for a subset of its edges that are relevant to some problem . The found subset must be internally consistent (i . e . we have to check for cancelation ef fects between mutually exclusive assumptions) . Consider the qualitative theory (Iwasaki , 1989) of Figure 2 . In that figure : $ all vertices can take one of three values : UP , DOWN , or STEADY ; "" $ X ÅÅ 5 Y denotes that Y being UP or DOWN could be explained by X being UP or DOWN respectively ; $$ $ X ÅÅ 5 Y denotes that Y being UP or DOWN could be explained by X being DOWN or UP respectively . Let us make some qualitative reasoning assumptions about Figure 2 : $ the conjunction of an UP and a DOWN can explain a STEADY ; $ no change can be explained in terms of a STEADY (i . e . a STEADY vertex has no children) . With these assumptions , we can expand Figure 2 in to Figure 3 . That figure contains one vertex for each possible state of the vertices of Figure 2 . It also contains and vertices that models combinations of influences (for example , aUp and bUp leads to cSteady ) . Figure 3 represents the superset of all explanations possible from Figure 2 ; i . e . it is an explicit ground version of Clancey’s QM and Breuker’s generic domain model . Given some inputs (denoted IN ) and some desired goals (denoted OUT ) , then we can use Figure 3 to generate a set of explanatory proofs (denoted P ) . For example , 310 T . MENZIES &008 &007 xSteady xUp yUp dUp aUp eUp cUp gUp bDown fUp &003 &001 cSteady fSteady &005 &004 &002 xDown yDown &006 dDown aDown eDown dSteady cDown gDown bUp fDown F IGURE 3 . The edges E tacit in Figure 2 . if IN # % aUp , bUP & OUT # % dUp , eUp , fDown & then all the proofs which can link members of IN to members of OUT across Figure 3 are : p(1) # aUp 5 xUp 5 yUp 5 dUp p(2) # aUp 5 cUp 5 gUp 5 dUp p(3) # aUp 5 cUp 5 gUp 5 eUp p(4) # bUp 5 cDown 5 gDown 5 fDown p(5) # bUp 5 fDown Some of these proofs are contradictory since that make conflicting assumptions . An assumption is a literal that is not one of the known FACTS (typically , FACTS # IN " OUT ) . Our assumptions are % xUp , yUp , cUp , gUp , cDown , gDown & . If we assume that an entity can’t be in two dif ferent states at the same time , then the following assumptions are conflicting and controversial : % cUp , gUp , cDown , gDown & . Note that , in Figure 2 , g is fully determined by c . Therefore , in terms of sorting out the various possibilities , the key controversial assumptions are % cUp , gUp & and % cDown , gDown & . Depending on which controversial assumptions we adopt , we can believe dif ferent things . In this example , we have two possibilities : one for % cUp , dUp & and one for % cDown , dDown & . The proofs that are consistent with % cUp , dUp & are % P , P , P , P & 1 2 3 5 and the proofs that are consistent with % cDown , dDown & are % P , P , P & . The union of 1 4 5 the proofs that we can believe at the same time are the Clancey SSM or the APPLICATIONS OF ABDUCTION : KNOWLEDGE-LEVEL MODELLING 311 xUp yUp dUp aUp eUp cUp gUp bUp fDown F IGURE 4 . Case model 4 1 : the union of proofs that are consistent with % cUp , gUp & . Breuker case model (we will call them worlds below) . There are two such case models , shown in Figure 4 and Figure 5 . Queries can be executed over each case model to generate Breuker’s argument structures or conclusions . For example , in case model 4 1 (Figure 4) , an argument structure for the conclusion dUp could be aUp 5 xUp 5 yUp 5 dUp . 3 . Abduction We believe that abduction is a powerful framework for describing the above theory subset extraction process . In this section , we repeat the above example in terms of HT4 (Menzies , 1995 c ) , our preferred abductive framework . In the next section , we will argue that many KL tasks are just dif ferent ways of calling HT4 . B 3 . 1 . DEFINITIONS Informally , abduction is typically defined as inference to the best explanation (e . g . Rourke , 1990) . Given % , & , and the rule R : % ! & , then deduction is using the rule 1 and its preconditions to make a conclusion ( % ∧ R é & ) ; induction is learning R 1 1 after seeing numerous examples of & and % ; and abduction is using the postcondi- tion and the rule to assume that the precondition could explain the postcondition ( & ∧ R é % ) (Levesque , 1989) . Abduction is not a certain inference and its results 1 must be checked by an inference assessment operator [which we call BEST and Bylander , Allemang , Tanner & Josephson (1991) call the plausbility operator pl ] . 3 . 2 . HT4 AND ABDUCTION More formally , abduction is the search for assumptions A which , when combined with some theory T achieves some set of goals OUT without causing some contradiction (Eshghi , 1993) . That is : EQ : V " A ! OUT 1 EQ 2 : T " A Ö ! " xUp yUp dUp aUp cDown gDown bDown fDown F IGURE 5 . Case model 4 2 : the union of proofs that are consistent with % cDown , gDown & . 312 T . MENZIES While abduction can be used to generate explanation engines (see Section 4 . 3) , we believe that EQ and EQ are more than just a description of ‘‘inference to the best 1 2 explanation’’ . EQ and EQ can be summarized as follows : make what inferences 1 2 you can that are relevant to some goal , without causing any contradictions . Note that the proof trees used to solve EQ and EQ are the case models / SSMs / worlds 1 2 we seek to compute . To execute HT4 , the user must supply a theory T (e . g . T # Figure 2) comprising a 1 set of uniquely labelled statements S . For example , from Figure 2 , we could say x that : s[1] # plus – plus(a , c) . s[2] # minus – minus(b , c) . etc . An S statement is like a macro that expands into the super-set of explanations i acceptable to the author of S . This super-set is the search space for the proof i generation . We represent this search space as a dependency graph D . D is directed and possibly cyclic . Figure 3 shows D , the dependency graph generated from T . D 1 1 is an and-or graph comprising ## V a n d , V o r $ , E , I $ ; i . e . a set of directed edges E connecting vertices V containing invariants I . I is defined in the negative ; i . e . — l I means that no invariant violation has occurred . Each edge E and vertex V is x y labelled with the Z that generated it . Figure 3 contains sample and-vertices and z or-vertices . For example : $ xUp is an or-vertex which we can believe if we also believe dUp or aUp . $ &OO3 is an and-vertex which we can believe if we also believe gUp and bUp (but see Section 4 . 2 for alternative ways of handling and-vertices) . Not shown in Figure 3 are the invariants I . For a qualitative domain , where entities can have one of a finite number of mutually exclusive values , the invariants are merely all pairs of mutually exclusive assignments ; e . g . : %i(X , Y) : X and Y cannot be believed together i(aUp , aSteady) . i(aSteady , aUp) . i(aUp , aDown) . i(aDown , aUp) . i(bUp , bSteady) . i(bSteady , bUp) . i(bUp , bDown) . i(bDown , bUp) . etc . 3 . 3 . THE MODEL COMPILER When converting T to D , a model compiler is required to capture any special i i domain semantics . For example , in a qualitative reasoning domain , we can reach a STEADY via a conjunction of two competing upstream influences (e . g . &003 ) . In practice , these model compilers are very small . Our qualitative domain compiler is less than 100 lines of Smalltalk . HT4-style inference is feasible for representations that support such a translator between T and D . Recall that D is an explicit and-or graph of literals (positive or negative propositions) that represents the superset of explanations acceptable to the author of T . Such and-or graphs can be extracted from many representations APPLICATIONS OF ABDUCTION : KNOWLEDGE-LEVEL MODELLING 313 including propositional expert systems and certain types of equational systems (Iwasaki & Simon , 1986 ; Iwasaki , 1988) . HT4 could also be used for first-order theories , but only where that theory can be partially evaluated to an equivalent ground (i . e . no variables) theory . Once such a model-compiler is available , then the practical limit to HT4 is the size of D . These limits are explored further in Section 5 . 3 . 4 . PROOFS OF OUT PUTS HT4 extracts subsets of E which are relevant to some user-supplied TASK . Each TASK is a triple # IN , OUT , BEST $ . Each task comprises some OUT puts to be x reached , given some IN put ( OUT ‘ V and IN ‘ V ) . IN can either be a member of the known FACTS or a DEFAULT belief which we can assume if it proves convenient to do so . Typically , FACTS # IN " OUT . If there is more than one way to achie ! e the TASK , then the BEST operator selects the preferred way(s) . To reach a particular output OUT ! OUT , we must find a proof tree P using z x vertices P used whose single leaf is OUT and whose roots are from IN (denoted x z P roots ‘ IN ) . All immediate parent vertices of all and-vertices in a proof must also x appear in that proof . One parent of all or-vertices in a proof must also appear in that proof unless V or ! IN (i . e . is an acceptable root of a proof) . No subset of P used may y x contradict the FACTS ; e . g . for invariants of arity 2 : — l ( V y ! P u xsed ∧ V z ! FACTS ∧ I ( V y , V z )) 3 . 5 . ASSUMPTION SETS The union of the vertices used in all proofs that are not from the FACTS is the HT4 assumption set A ; i . e . ’ ( A # ! % V ! P used & $ FACTS y x V y Recall from the above that the proofs in our example made the assumptions : a # % xUp , yUp , cUp , gUp , cDown , gDown & The union of the subsets of A which violate I are the contro ! ersial assumptions A : C A # ! % V ! A ∧ V ! A ∧ I ( V , V ) & C x y x y V x The controversial assumptions of our example were : ac # % cUp , gUp , cDown , gDown & The base contro ! ersial assumptions ( A ) are the controversial assumptions which B 314 T . MENZIES have no controversial assumptions in their ancestors (i . e . are not downstream of any other controversial assumptions) . The base controversial assumptions of our example are : ab # % cUp , cDown & 3 . 6 . WORLD GENERATION Maximal consistent subsets of P (i . e . maximal with respect to size , consistent with respect to I ) are grouped together into what we call worlds W ( W ‘ E ) (recall that i world ) case model ) SSM) . Each world W contains a consistent set of beliefs that i are relevant to the TASK . The union of the vertices used in the proofs of W is i denoted W used . i In terms of separating the proofs into worlds , A are the crucial assumptions . We B call the maximal consistent subsets of A the en ! ironments ENV ( ENV ‘ A ‘ B i B A ‘ A ‘ V ) . The environments of our example are : C env(1) # % cUp & env(2) # % cDown & The union of the proofs that do not contradict ENV is the world W . One world is i i defined for each environment ; i . e . " W " # " ENV " . In order to check for non- contradiction , we use I to find the vertices that are forbidden by each proof : P forbids # ! % V ! P used ∧ I ( V , V ) & j k j k l V i For example , P forbids # % bDown , bSteady , fUp , fSteady & . 5 A proof P belongs in world W if its forbids set does not intersect with ENV ; i . e . : j i i * + W # ! P forbids ! ENV # C i j i P j Note that each proof can exist in multiple worlds . The worlds of our example are : w(1) # % p(1) , p(2) , p(3) , p(5) & w(2) # % p(1) , p(4) , p(5) & W is shown in Figure 4 and W is shown in Figure 5 . 1 2 3 . 7 . ASSESSING WORLDS For any world W , W causes are the members of IN found in W ( W causes # W used ! i i i i i IN ) . The achievable or co ! ered goals OUT in W are the members of OUT found in i that world ( W co ! ered # W used ! OUT ) . Continuing our example : i i causes(w(1)) # % aUp , bUp & causes(w(2)) # % aUp , bUp &

Description:
A single inference procedure (abduction) can operationalise a wide variety of Further, abduction can execute in vague and conflicting domains.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.