A field guide to mechanisms: part I Holly Andersen Simon Fraser University [email protected] Abstract: In this field guide, I distinguish five separate senses with which the term ‘mechanism’ is used in contemporary philosophy of science. Many of these senses have overlapping areas of application but involve distinct philosophical claims and characterize the target mechanisms in relevantly different ways. This field guide will clarify the key features of each sense and introduce some main debates, distinguishing those that transpire within a given sense from those that are best understood as concerning distinct senses. The ‘new mechanisms’ sense is at the center of most of these contemporary debates, and will be treated at greater length; subsequent senses of mechanism will be primarily distinguished from this one. In part I of this paper, I distinguish two senses of the term ‘mechanism’, both of which are explicitly hierarchical and nested in character, such that any given mechanism is comprised of smaller sub-‐mechanisms, in turn comprised of yet smaller sub-‐sub-‐ mechanisms, and so on. While both of the senses discussed here are anti-‐reductive, they differ in their focus on scientific practice versus metaphysics, in the degree of regularity they attribute to mechanisms, and in terms of their relationships to the discussions of mechanisms in the history of philosophy and science. Keywords: mechanisms; causation; explanation; reduction; methodology 0) Introduction Talk of mechanisms is central to a variety of recent debates in philosophy of science. For those working outside of these debates, it can be difficult to get a clear sense of what all the talk of ‘new mechanisms’ is about. This two-‐part field guide is intended to provide an overview of the main new sense of mechanism that has been the primary focus of discussion, and to distinguish this new sense from other related but relevantly different senses in which the term mechanism appears in philosophy of science. This field guide begins by a concise overview of the literature on ‘new mechanisms’, and then turns to distinguishing and comparing other notions of mechanism to this one. 1 This field guide offers taxonomic classifications of species of mechanism, with key distinguishing markings of each species. These taxonomic distinctions have not been utilized in debate involving ‘mechanisms’ but are motivated out of the kinds of characterizations and debates that have multiplied on this topic recently. In elaborating each distinct sense, I am thereby arguing that each involves a unique set of ontological, methodological, explanatory, and anti-‐/reductive commitments. Claims that are true of one sense will fail of others; as such, the senses are not interchangeable, even though they are often presumed to be (especially mechanism 1 and mechanism ). 2 The division between parts I and II classifies types of mechanisms in terms of whether or not they are explicitly anti-‐reductive. Here in part I, I focus on two senses that include an explicitly tiered ontology as an alternative to reduction. These approaches to mechanisms concern ways to individuate and connect levels, especially but not limited to levels as they are studied in the sciences, while rejecting that this constitutes a reduction of higher levels to lower levels. This anti-‐ reductive approach to mechanisms aims to provide explanatory autonomy to the so-‐ called special sciences, while still grounding their objects of investigation firmly in the physical world. These two senses can be distinguished by differing in 3 major characteristics: the first emphasizes the role of mechanisms in various aspects of scientific practice, while the second emphasizes a metaphysical role for mechanisms; the first attributes some degree of regularity to mechanisms, while the second allows any unique causal chain to count as a mechanism; and while the first offers something novel to the ongoing philosophical discussion of mechanisms, the second is more closely aligned with the historical notion of mechanism. These characteristics are mutually supportive; for instance, an emphasis on scientific practice leads clearly to a focus on regularities as targets for experimentation, while an emphasis on metaphysics connects much more closely to the historical discussion of mechanisms in natural philosophy. 2 Each section of this field guide will begin by briefly characterizing the most salient philosophical features of the relevant species of mechanism, including the kind of discussion in which it most frequently appears. I will then briefly discuss the ontological commitments of each sense, their methodological implications, and their role in explanation, respectively. Each section includes a comparison distinguishing it from other related senses of mechanism. 1) Mechanism : Mechanisms as integral to scientific practice 1 This is the ‘new mechanism’ approach that is arguably the primary sense of the term mechanism in recent discussion. This species of mechanism is very commonly found in discussions of explanation in the sciences, as distinct, for instance, from explanation in history or of action. It comprises several claims. One is the ontological claim that the phenomena studied by many sciences, especially so-‐called higher-‐level sciences like biology, have a particular hierarchical structure comprised of nested levels. Each level involves entities organized in various ways and connected via causal interactions or activities, constituting or giving rise to a pattern that recurs under specific identifiable circumstances. These patterns are the regularities that constitute the phenomena studied by these sciences. Such mechanisms provide non-‐arbitrary ways to divide parts of the world into levels of physical size and organization, and to understand the connections between different levels, without having to reduce or eliminate higher levels or treat them as merely apparent or epiphenomenal. A second claim is that the methodology of many sciences reflects this ontological structure of their target phenomena, by isolating consistent patterns or regularities in the world and then decomposing them into constituent entities, causal connections, and spatio-‐temporal organization. The emphasis is on the practice of science. A third claim, central to this sense, concerns explanation in such sciences, 3 namely, that the explanations they offer reflect this ontology. Explanations are of regularly recurring phenomena in the physical world that are the end product of, or are constituted by, the operation of such mechanisms; such regularities are to be explained by providing details about the mechanism(s) responsible for producing them. The trajectory leading up to this sense of mechanism is familiar. As logical empiricism waned in the middle of the 20th century, philosophers of science focused on deduction from universal laws as the primary form of explanation in science (e.g. Hempel and Oppenheim 1948, Hempel 1963). On this view, an explanation involves a general law plus a set of initial conditions, from which the explanandum could be deduced.1 A variety of problems plagued the deductive-‐nomological account of explanation (see, for instance, Salmon 1978). One clear issue was the apparent lack of suitable laws in biology to serve in a deduction. This posed an unfortunate dilemma: either biology and related sciences do not really explain, or the D-‐N account applies only narrowly to some explanations, mainly in physics. Laws can be reconstrued in ways that render them more applicable in biological sciences (Mitchell 1997), but many still found the D-‐N model of explanation unsatisfactory in biological contexts. This ‘new mechanism’ approach arose in response to many of the issues raised with the D-‐N model of explanation. It differed from the D-‐N account in terms of what it took the sciences to be investigating, how those investigations generally proceed, and the explanatory results of those investigations. Ontologically, it shifted the emphasis away from universal laws and nomic necessity, towards recurrent patterns of causal structure, with a much more limited scope of generalizability. Methodologically, it took the sciences to be engaged in finding more and more detail, by targeting and decomposing the mechanisms that support limited regularities, 1 On this view, the deductive arguments that rely on universal laws to show the necessity of the explanandum also have an inductive counterpart, relying on statistical generalizations that raise the probability of the explanandum. 4 rather than seeking ever broader and more abstract generalizations. These ontological and methodological views support an account of explanation that eschews propositionally structured laws and logically valid arguments, instead relying on mechanism models, of varying levels of descriptive specificity, involving real entities, their activities, and their organization into coherent processes that recur under appropriate circumstances. Finally, this new sense of mechanism is deeply anti-‐reductionist: science may uncover explanatory or ontological connections between higher and lower levels, but does not thereby either eliminate or reduce the higher levels thus connected (Wimsatt 1994). The hierarchically structured, anti-‐reductionist approach involved in mechanisms holds that science provides genuine explanations that “bottom out” 1 without having to be grounded in some ultimate fundamental level (Machamer, Darden, and Craver 2000). Higher-‐level explanations are not viewed as placeholders for some ‘real’, microphysical, explanation; the focus is instead on integrating and connecting levels (Glennan 1995, 2002, 2005; Darden and Craver 2009). Even if mechanisms in biology are ultimately composed of sub-‐sub-‐submechanisms in physics, this does not meant that biological phenomena explained by such mechanisms are thereby reduced to the lower-‐level mechanisms. This anti-‐reductive stance has ontological consequences. Methodologies for investigating levels of recurrent mechanisms can proceed in relative autonomy, neither affirming nor denying any ultimate ontological relationship between different branches of science, scientific theories, or phenomena. Mechanism thus 1 imposes some distance between, on the one hand, normative epistemological or methodological claims about the most effective ways to investigate the world, and, on the other hand, the underlying nature of that world. It is not explicitly anti-‐ metaphysical, but rather metaphysically agnostic. The anti-‐reductive character of mechanism allows us to make methodological recommendations about 1 investigating the world (see especially Bechtel and Richardson 1992 and Darden 5 2002) without thereby committing ourselves to a single account of what that world is like. Mechanism is often elaborated as part of a detailed look at the actual investigatory 1 practices of the sciences, especially biological sciences. Bechtel and Richardson (1993; see also Bechtel and Abrahamsen 2005) characterize scientific discovery in the biological sciences in terms of localizing and decomposing mechanisms. Instead of searching for universal laws, many scientists are engaged in the task of identifying regular phenomena and the precise circumstances under which they transpire, and the locus of control by which mechanisms can be manipulated. Some target regularity must first be delineated – what is the phenomenon to be explained? This often proceeds by investigating the precise spatio-‐temporal boundaries of the regularity, including parameter values that modulate how it occurs and supporting environmental factors outside of the mechanism itself. Localized mechanisms can be decomposed into constituent elements or components, their interactions, and the organization of those elements into a coherent and re-‐identifiable process. Once localized and decomposed, the delineated mechanism explains why the identified regularity occurs as it does, under the conditions that it does. The way in which mechanisms are investigated shapes the kinds of explanations in 1 which those mechanisms figure. Explanations can involve a greater or lesser degree of specificity, depending on the state of scientific knowledge or the context in which a given explanation is provided. For example, Craver and Darden (2001), Darden (2002), Craver (2007), and Darden (2008) offer mechanism sketches, mechanism schemata, and fully developed mechanisms as identifiable stages involved in the discovery of mechanisms. Mechanism schemata are abstract descriptions of mechanisms that can be instantiated to yield descriptions of particular mechanisms. The term mechanism schemata is fitting because their components are placeholders that 6 can be filled in with detailed stages between the setup and termination. … Mechanism sketches, in contrast to mechanism schemata, are abstract descriptions of mechanisms that cannot yet be filled in (Craver and Darden 2001, 120). Darden calls these distinctions “advisory”: neither simply descriptive, nor purely prescriptive, they provide a set of terms and concepts for scientists that can be genuinely useful in structuring research, while recognizing that these terms and concepts have been developed by considering what many scientists are already doing. Schemata and sketches vary in terms of the amount of detail they fill in about the mechanism(s) in questions and the amount of possibility they leave open for how that mechanism might be instantiated. The idea is that a mechanism sketch places constraints on the kind of mechanism that could instantiate it. The first stage of discovery of a mechanism may consist in such a sketch that guides further research by narrowing the range of possible kinds of mechanisms to be investigated. A fuller set of constraints may be provided by mechanism schemata, where components and their connecting activities have sufficient constraints placed on them that researchers can begin filling in physical details for particular mechanisms. A single schema may be instantiated by several distinct mechanisms that fill in the placeholder components with different entities or activities that fulfill broadly similar functions. This highlights the need to distinguish between mechanisms , which are in the 1 world, and models of mechanisms (e.g. Glennan 2005, Illari and Williamson 2010). 1 This distinction figures in the debate of what it is in virtue of which mechanisms 1 are explanatory. Drawing from Salmon (1984), the ontic conception of mechanisms holds that mechanisms are represented in models and theories in the sciences, but are not identical with those representational devices. They are instead ‘out there’ in the world. This makes an important difference when considered in terms of 7 explanation: do semantic or syntactic relationships between elements of a model-‐ theoretic representation do the explanatory work in their own right, or do they merely point to or exhibit the causal relationships in the world that do the explanatory work? Wright (2012) argues against this ontic conception, holding instead that explanation is a communicative process for the purpose of understanding which must thus involve models of mechanisms. Many models of mechanisms are not propositionally structured, but are instead conveyed using 1 diagrammatic or visual forms of representation (Darden and Craver 2002, Perini 2005a, 2005b). This debate concerns the role that mechanism plays in explanation: 1 do mechanism explanations involve physical mechanisms themselves, or models of those mechanisms? It has consequences that reach beyond the discussion simply of mecahnisms , however, by undermining general accounts of explanation that rely 1 on, for instance, logical entailment relationships between premises in arguments to characterize explanation (Strevens 2008). If mechanism models figure in 1 explanations, diagrammatic or other visual representations of mechanisms lack the 1 requisite propositional structure to figure in such logical relationships; if physical mechanisms themselves figure, they lack such features even more obviously. 1 The extent to which mechanisms constrain ontological commitments is also a point 1 of dispute. Some of these debates are best understood in terms of a univocal sense of mechanism (namely, mechanism ), while others involve tension between 1 different senses of mechanism. Two examples of intra-‐sense debate concern how to best characterize the internal structure of mechanisms, and the extent of ontological commitments entailed by mechanism . For the first example, there are 1 disagreements about how to best describe the process of a mechanism in action. Machamer, Darden, and Craver (2000) utilize start-‐up conditions that trigger the mechanism, and termination conditions that are the last stage within the mechanism. Using the example of circadian rhythms, Bechtel and Abrahamsen (2010) argue instead that mechanisms are often cyclical, and therefore lack clear start-‐up or termination conditions. 8 The second example involves disagreement about how much ontological commitment should accompany mechanism . While some authors who defend this 1 new mechanism approach do so in an ontologically agnostic way (for instance, Bechtel and Richardson 1993), mechanism is clearly well-‐suited to certain kinds of 1 ontological commitments.2 For instance, Machamer, Darden, and Craver (2000) argue for a dualistic entity-‐activity ontology to ground the mechanistic account of 1 explanation. They characterize mechanisms as “entities and activities organized such that they are productive of regular changes from start or set-‐up conditions to finish or termination conditions” (2000, 3). Mechanisms are organized chains of 1 entities connected via productive activities of those entities; the organized activities provide both continuity to the mechanism and regularity of operation (ibid.). Phenomena to be explained via mechanisms are either the final product that results once termination conditions are reached or a higher-‐level regularity to which the mechanism gives rise. Thus, mechanisms can explain (at least) two ontological kinds of target phenomenon. One kind is the effects of causal relationships, where the explanandum is the final stage in an often complex causal chain at the same level as the rest of the entities and activities in the mechanism. The second kind is phenomena at a higher level than the explanans, where causal activities connect the entities at a lower level, and the entire mechanism’s operation constitutes the higher-‐level phenomenon. Machamer, Darden, and Craver (2000) explicitly aim to offer a view of mechanisms 1 that is compatible with Salmon’s (1984) process account of causation. In contrast to their commitment to the process account, the causal relationships binding mechanisms together could be construed in terms of counterfactuals, or 1 dispositions, or capacities (e.g. Ilari and Williamson 2010). Accordingly, we see that mechanism is not itself an account of causation (this will be more fully explored in 1 2 This is not to say that mechanisms are compatible with just any ontology: the 1 epistemological or methodological features of the new mechanisms approach place compatibility constraints on ontological commitments. Rather, the point here is that these constraints are not enough to dictate a single unique ontology. 9 the next section), however much claims about causation figures in ongoing debates within the mechanisms literature. Williamson’s (2011) criterion for being a mechanistic theory of causality, that “two events are causally connected if and only if they are connected by an underlying physical mechanism of the appropriate sort” (421), is not met by mechanisms . 1 The anti-‐reductive aspect of mechanisms generates questions about interlevel 1 causation; this is a debate concerning causal relationships within mechanisms , not 1 about the nature of causation per se. The nested, hierarchical structure of mechanisms allows for non-‐arbitrary ways to individuate levels in the world, in a local and context-‐sensitive rather than broad or generally applicable way. It also raises the question of whether direct causal relationships between entities or processes at different levels are possible.3 Craver and Bechtel (2007) reject the possibility of interlevel causation. They argue for a differentiation of levels such that it is only meaningful to speak of higher and lower levels within a single given mechanism. The levels in a mechanism form a hierarchy structured by the constitutive relationships between phenomena and the mechanisms that give rise to them. Craver and Bechtel note a common stricture on causal relata, such that parts of a whole cannot directly enter into causal relationships with that whole. They conclude that there is no meaningful way to speak of causal relationships between different levels within a mechanism. Either those relationships must be non-‐causal and constitutive, or they must not be between genuinely different levels, since they occur between different mechanisms and levels are only defined within individual mechanisms. This conclusion, however, is in tension with much scientific practice, where levels are often treated as robust differentiations across multiple mechanisms. Mitchell (2008) provides a number of examples of what she calls multilevel causation and 3 There are many ways to construe levels; Craver (2007) offers a different kind of field guide to many of those ways. Here, I focus on levels within a mechanism, which are defined in terms of nested mechanisms. 10
Description: