ebook img

Neo-Aristotelian Confucianism? PDF

20 Pages·2014·0.24 MB·English
by  
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Neo-Aristotelian Confucianism?

70 International Journal of Area Studies 8:1, 2013 DOI: 10.2478/ijas-2013-0004 Vytis silius Vilnius uniVersity Neo-Aristotelian Confucianism? Applicability of virtue ethics in early Confucian studies Abstract Since the 80’s of the last century a trend has emerged in the English language literature on Chinese thought that suggests reading early Confucian texts as a form of virtue ethics. However, Alasdair MacIntyre has presented early Confucian and Aristotle’s thoughts as incommensurable thought systems and doubted that notions and statements of one incommensurable thought system can be adequately expressed and addressed within the framework of another. This article discusses MacIntyre’s position and two strategies – employed by the proponents of virtue ethics interpretation of early Confucian texts – of meeting MacIntyre’s challenge. The article attempts to show that none of the responses were successful, thus leaving the quest for the most adequate philosophical framework to interpret early Confucian ethical thought open. Keywords: early Confucianism, virtue ethics, incommensurability, comparative philosophy Introduction1 Since the 80’s of the last century a trend has emerged in the English language literature on Chinese thought that suggests reading early Confucian texts as a form of virtue ethics with its roots in Aristotle’s thought and its contemporary explication primarily associated with the writings of Alasdair MacIntyre. This interpretation contrasts early Confucian ethics with modern moral theories of deontology and consequentialism and sees Confucians as emphasizing a long-term cultivation of benevolent character traits in human beings, instead of formulating simple and universal principles of right conduct. This has led some scholars to conceptualization of early Confucian ethical thought in virtue ethics terms and translation of key ethical terms in aretaic vocabulary. A number of the most distinguished English-writing scholars of Chinese thought has supported the virtue ethics interpretation of early Confucians2. This interpretation has been successful in the sense that it has contributed to the renewed and still increasing interest of contemporary Western moral philosophers in early Confucian ethical writings. However, in a volume dedicated to comparative studies Alasdair MacIntyre Brought to you by | LMBA Lithuanian Research Library Consortium Authenticated Download Date | 4/28/17 1:17 PM VYTIS SILIUS. Neo-Aristotelian Confucianism? 71 has published an article where he has presented early Confucian and Aristotle’s thoughts as incommensurable thought systems and have explicitly expressed doubt that notions and statements of one incommensurable thought system can be adequately expressed and addressed within the framework of another. The position MacIntyre argued for in this article has been taken by proponents of Confucian virtue ethics as challenge for their approach3. The challenge is even more pressing, as it was formulated by the thinker, whose ideas have largely shaped the virtue ethics approach in general. In what follows, I will firstly present main ideas on incommensurability in MacIntyre’s article. Against that background, I will summarize several responses formulated specifically by the proponents of virtue ethics interpretation of Confucian thought. At the centre of this investigation are the scholars who attempt to meet MacIntyre’s challenge and stay in a neo-Aristotelian framework while comparing different traditions. We will put these responses into two groups – the “negative” (Yu Jiyuan, May Sim), where the goal of response is to refute MacIntyre’s critique by showing that it is contradictory, wrong, and/or harmful; and the “positive” (Bryan Van Norden), where the goal of response is to meet MacIntyre’s challenge by working out a comparative framework that would be immune to the critique voiced by MacIntyre. My claim throughout this article is that none of the responses from Confucian virtue ethics perspective were successful, as the negative ones tend to misread MacIntyre’s initial claims and the positive one falls short of providing truly neutral ground for comparison of early Confucian and Aristotelian or neo-Aristotelian ethical ideas, impossibility of which was claimed by MacIntyre. MacIntyre and incommensurability of the rival theories According to Richard J. Bernstein “incommensurability” was thrust into the centre of Anglo-American philosophical debates because of Thomas Kuhn’s provocative book, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Bernstein 1991, 87). Although Kuhn in his book was exclusively interested in the incommensura- bility of scientific paradigms, the idea was soon “generalized and extended to problems and contexts far beyond Kuhn’s original concern to analyze scientific inquiry” (ibid, 89). Bernstein discusses Richard Rorty’s Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature and Alasdair MacIntyre’s Whose Justice? Which Rationality? as prominent examples of the extended use of the term. MacIntyre further extends the use of the term in his 1991 article “Incommen- surability, Truth, and the Conversation Between Confucians and Aristotelians About the Virtues”, where the idea of incommensurability was explicitly applied to intercultural studies. Some conceptual problems can be noted here, as the term “incommensurability” was used by Kuhn mainly in reference to scientific theories that have predictive value and make truth claims. It is Brought to you by | LMBA Lithuanian Research Library Consortium Authenticated Download Date | 4/28/17 1:17 PM 72 International Journal of Area Studies 8:1, 2013 an open question if we can take, at least, “Confucians” as working within a framework of a theory with its unique set of predictions and truth claims. If we understand Confucians as primarily engaged in practical activity, rather than theorisation of it, can we still apply the term “incommensurability” referring to Confucian practice4? Since this conceptual issue was not questioned in responses to MacIntyre’s use of incommensurability by scholars I am examining, I will not address this theme in my paper. In his article in 1991 MacIntyre discusses comparative philosophy that takes upon a task to explain, evaluate and compare Aristotelian and Confucian approaches to ethical issues by putting these two thought systems into one – neo-Aristotelian – conceptual framework. In this article MacIntyre treats early Confucian and Aristotelian though systems as incommensurable. According to MacIntyre, the incommensurability is “a relationship between two or more systems of thought and practice, each embodying its own peculiar conceptual scheme, over a certain period of time” (MacIntyre 1991, 109). The peculiarity of any given thought system, according to MacIntyre, is so pervasive that it manifests itself not only in the different concepts used by adherents of that system of thought and practice, but also in different and specific for that system rules and ways of argumentation, different standards and measures of interpretation, explanation, and justification, different norms of achievement, and so on. Because it is an obvious fact that cultures and systems of thought and practice are dynamic entities that change over time, MacIntyre acknowledges that the systems that were incommensurable at one point of the history may become commensurable at the other. However, during the time of incommensurability, according to MacIntyre, It will be the case that those who inhabit each of the two or more rival schemes of thought and practice embody them in their beliefs, actions, judgments, and arguments in such a way that it is both the case that the members of the two or more rival parties can agree, each from their own point of view, that they are referring to, characterizing, and conducting their inquiries about what is indeed one and the same subject matter, and yet also in their characterizations of and questions about that subject matter employ, to some large and significant degree, concepts whose applicability entails the nonapplicability, the vacuousness, of the conceptual scheme or schemes employed by their rivals (MacIntyre 1991, 109-10). MacIntyre suggests that incommensurable systems will share certain structure that will enable them to agree that the subject matter of their interest is the same, but, nevertheless, It is at a second level of characterization that predicates are applied in accordance with standards internal to and peculiar to each of the rival standpoints and such that each set of standard excludes the possibility of application for key predicates of its rivals. And this use of predicates will give expression to distinctive modes Brought to you by | LMBA Lithuanian Research Library Consortium Authenticated Download Date | 4/28/17 1:17 PM VYTIS SILIUS. Neo-Aristotelian Confucianism? 73 of observation, of seeing as and of imagining, as well as of reasoning (MacIntyre 1991, 110). There are several important points for comparative philosophers that MacIntyre draws from observations of incommensurability of thought systems. The first point that goes throughout the whole article as one of the main themes is that there can be no neutral and at the same time meaningful standpoint, from which we could compare two rival systems of thought and practice. As MacIntyre puts it, we could supply an account neutral with respect to any two rival systems, but such an account would be “at so bare a level of characterization that it will be equally compatible with far too many rival bodies of theory” (MacIntyre 1991, 105). Thus, either the standpoint of comparison is universal because it is so neutral that it does not say much substantially, or it is, rather, a specific standpoint with its own peculiar standards, implications, and corollaries. However, there are scholars who seem to disagree with MacIntyre on this point. In the last section of this article I will present Bryan Van Norden’s distinction between “thin” and “thick” accounts of theory, which I take as an attempt to provide such theoretically neutral grounds for comparison. The second and related point is that the lack of universal and neutral standpoint for comparison makes it obvious that even the statement of the nature of contrast between the two rival systems of thought and practice is problematic, because it is very likely to assume a certain specific view of what counts as problematic issue and to engage into equally specific way of how to formulate and solve that issue. If, according to MacIntyre, we are dealing with two incommensurable systems it will mean that even before starting to compare we have already chosen a specific framework that makes one of the incommensurable systems more at home than the other. For example, without any particular reference to Aristotelian ethics, Antonio Cua tries to present early Confucian ethics as an “ethics of virtue”. For Cua, the main goal of his “conceptual experiment” is an attempt to reconstruct what he have called “relatively loose system of action-guides” of early Confucianism as “ethics of virtue with a coherent conceptual scheme” (Cua 1998, 1; 271). We can see that the normative standards that support Cua’s qualification of tradition and interpretation in terms of “loose” and “coherent” and to favour one over the other were taken not from early Confucians. And even “incommensurability” arises as a problem, as it was noted before, only when theory is given primacy over practical engagement. As Hall and Ames point out, “despite the fact that MacIntyre is well aware that the Confucian moral vision depends little on what we would take to be theoretical or conceptual claims, he is still insistent that the comparison be pursued, if at all, at this level because the ultimate goal of such comparison is to determine the truth or falsity of claims made” (Hall and Ames 1998, xii-xiii). However, MacIntyre is well aware of this point, as he says of his own comparison, “up to this point, without acknowledging it, I have been characterizing the differences between Aristotelianism and Brought to you by | LMBA Lithuanian Research Library Consortium Authenticated Download Date | 4/28/17 1:17 PM 74 International Journal of Area Studies 8:1, 2013 Confucianism from what is more generally a Western and more specifically an Aristotelian point of view” (MacIntyre 1991, 107-8). The third point deals with the relation between incommensurability, translatability and the issue that will be very important for MacIntyre’s critics – possibility for mutual understanding between the two different cultures. MacIntyre points out in his example with Galileo’s move away from impetus theory of Aristotelian physics, that although the last adepts of Aristotelian physics and Galileo all did speak the same natural languages, the theories they promoted were incommensurable. According to MacIntyre, even if the shift in perspective and theoretical standpoint required from Galileo the enrichment of the terminology and idiom of the natural language he used, this change still happened within the same natural language. In other words, Galileo was not dealing with problems of translation. This shows, according to MacIntyre, that translatability does not entail commensurability, but it “surely must be, one initial step toward making possible a type of conversation between originally incommensurable standpoints which could over time transform their relationship” (MacIntyre 1991, 111). However, as MacIntyre explicitly suggests, when the incommensurability arises from untranslatability of the natural or technical languages, in which the rival systems of thought and practice are expressed, it does not follow that all the mutual understanding is precluded. “But such understanding is possible only for those adherents of each standpoint who are able to learn the language of the rival standpoint, so that they acquire, so far as possible, that other language as a second first language” (MacIntyre 1991, 111). According to MacIntyre, understanding comes not through the comparison that proceeds from asking the adherents of the rival system questions that are important in one’s own system of thought and practice and, then, requests or expects the answers that would comply with the relevant standards of one’s own tradition. Understanding comes from the immersion into the rival system and from learning their specific ways of reasoning and expressing the results of that reasoning. Incommensurability thesis, as MacIntyre presents it, does not suggest the impenetrability and inaccessibility of the incommensurable systems to each other’s adherents, and does not maintain that nothing meaningful can be argued from one system against the other. However, it does suggest that it is impossible to adequately and fully reiterate the problematique of one system of thought with the conceptual framework of the other incommensurable system without losing the significant degree of meaning and uniqueness of that system5. In other words, our critique from the positions of one incommensurable system will very likely touch only the surface of the other incommensurable system and miss most crucial assumptions, areas of interest, and goals of the system in question. MacIntyre’s position is that we eventually may achieve understanding of the other thought system and even present a substantial critique unless we both start and finish our investigation of the incommensurable thought system Brought to you by | LMBA Lithuanian Research Library Consortium Authenticated Download Date | 4/28/17 1:17 PM VYTIS SILIUS. Neo-Aristotelian Confucianism? 75 by applying it to our own standards and conceptual frameworks. The fourth point MacIntyre directs more to Aristotelians, which shows that he admits that Confucian framework could probably render this aspect in comparative philosophy differently or find it irrelevant. MacIntyre suggests that the conceptual grasp of incommensurability helps to advance the conversation between two rival systems, because once Aristotelians understand that their rejection of the rival standpoint was “inevitable” as stemming from imposition of their standards of argumentation and justification upon the system that operates in rather different and incommensurable ways, “they would have to conclude that no rational encounter, no dialectical appeal to mutually acknowledged principles of any kind, whether principles embodied in shared established opinions or principles necessary for the achievements of scientific explanation and understanding, had taken place or could so far have taken place” (MacIntyre 1991, 112). This point helps to raise awareness that at this stage of the conversation between the rival systems of thought and practice no claims for truth by the parties of conversation can be made. Especially, if these claims were to resolve the problematic issues between theories and achieve a verdict of which system presents true statements on the nature of the subject matter. In other words, the concept of incommensurability makes one aware that there are other consistent and workable ways of describing and explaining the world reality. As MacIntyre puts it, “without rational encounter the rival theory becomes a subject matter concerning which we have not achieved that truth which is adaequatio intellectus ad rem” (MacIntyre 1991, 112). Recognition of incommensurability of two rival theories may foster more charitable treatment of the rival theory, allowing it to state its position in its own framework, and it prevents the temptation of reductionist treatment of world cultures. This point should be seen as MacIntyre’s suggestion to allow the rival system of thought and practice to be different from one’s own, that is, allowing it to operate in its natural modus, according to its natural standards. At the same time, because MacIntyre does not see cultures and systems of thoughts and practice inherent in these cultures as static and monolithic, but rather as changing through the course of their history, the incommensurability of two theoretical standpoints is not taken by MacIntyre as an unavoidable matter of fact that makes the rational encounter impossible. This leads us to the last point of MacIntyre’s incommensurability thesis, the suggestion that the rational debate and encounter between Aristotelian and Confucian systems can take place only by enriching the linguistic and conceptual resources of one’s own tradition to the point that it would enable the parties to provide the more adequate representation of each other. According to MacIntyre, That accurate representation will be of the other as a historically developing body of theory and practice, succeeding or failing at each stage, in the light of its own standards, in respect of the difficulties or problems internal to it. That Brought to you by | LMBA Lithuanian Research Library Consortium Authenticated Download Date | 4/28/17 1:17 PM 76 International Journal of Area Studies 8:1, 2013 is, what the Aristotelian will have had to provide for his or her own use will be a history of Confucianism written and understood from a Confucian point of view… (MacIntyre 1991, 117). According to MacIntyre, having constructed such history of the rival standpoint according to the internal standards of that rival account, having learned the conceptual apparatus that voices the position of that rival standpoint, an Aristotelian would not only be able to understand Confucianism, but also to engage into rational and critical discussion that could lead adherents of one system to recognize “rational inferiority” to the other rival and incompatible tradition. Rational dialogue would be possible here, because both parties would engage into dialogue consciously using the same framework of conversation, after “incorporating within their own structures of understanding an accurate representation of that standpoint and its history” (MacIntyre 1991, 117). MacIntyre finishes his paper with suggestions that should facilitate such conversation between two or more rival bodies of theory and practice that would not, in MacIntyre’s words, be “sterile”. First, he suggests that as comparative philosophers we should “understand our own standpoint in a way that renders it from our own point of view as problematic as possible and therefore as maximally vulnerable as possible to defeat by that rival” (MacIntyre 1991, 121). Then, MacIntyre claims, we have to make sure that “we do not allow ourselves to forget that in comparing two fundamental standpoints at odds with each other … we have no neutral, independent standpoint from which to do so” (MacIntyre 1991, 121). According to MacIntyre this means that we can compare Confucianism and Aristotelianism from the Confucian point of view, or from the Aristotelian point of view, or from some third, equally specific standpoint with its own internal structure, standards, and vocabulary, for example, Buddhist or Kantian. “But we cannot find any legitimate standing ground outside the context of the points of view” (MacIntyre 1991, 121). Thus already a way how we voice our disagreements, according to MacIntyre, should be the object of our disagreement, exactly because it is never culturally neutral. MacIntyre’s position was understood by many as arguing for radical impossibility of mutual understanding in the intercultural discussions and as openly threatening the very undertaking of comparative philosophers. In so far as MacIntyre denied the adequacy and appropriateness of straightforward comparison by reiterating the content of one system of thought and practice by the means and in the ways of its rival, MacIntyre did indeed question the validity of certain type of comparative studies. In Confucian studies many adherents of virtue ethics interpretation of early Confucians have taken MacIntyre’s position as a challenge for their own undertakings. It is especially acute problem in virtue ethics approach to Confucian texts, as the main thesis of this group of scholars – that early Confucian thought is best understood as a form of virtue ethics6 – can be seen as an attempt to express the sensibilities Brought to you by | LMBA Lithuanian Research Library Consortium Authenticated Download Date | 4/28/17 1:17 PM VYTIS SILIUS. Neo-Aristotelian Confucianism? 77 of one tradition with the vocabulary of other incommensurable tradition. Yu Jiyuan, for example, notes that MacIntyre’s version of incommensurability “threatens our project of comparing the ethics of Aristotle and Confucius”, but Yu, nevertheless, does not find MacIntyre’s “rejection of the possibility of the comparison between Aristotelianism and Confucianism to be acceptable” (Yu 2007, 6-7). In what follows, I will present two ways in which adherents of virtue ethics interpretation of early Confucians have tried to meet MacIntyre’s challenge. “Negative” responses to MacIntyre’s incommensurability challenge One of the recent studies committed to comparison of Confucius and Aristotle is a study by Yu Jiyuan, The Ethics of Confucius and Aristotle: Mirrors of Virtue (2007). Before proceeding to the comparison itself, Yu Jiyuan attempts to clear methodological issues in comparative philosophy against MacIntyre’s challenge of incommensurability. According to Yu Jiyuan, MacIntyre’s position “is not clear” and MacIntyre “seems to be caught in confusion” (Yu 2007, 7; 8). Where does Yu see this alleged confusion in MacIntyre’s position? Yu explains that MacIntyre’s understanding of the incommensurability of two rival systems is leading “to the impossibility of adjudicating their rival claims” (Yu 2007, 7), but MacIntyre supposedly allows rational encounter and, something that Yu finds ironic, MacIntyre draws his conclusion about the incommensurability of Confucianism and Aristotelianism “through comparative study of these two theories” (Yu 2007, 7). Thus Yu concludes that “MacIntyre seems to be caught in confusion between the result of comparative philosophy and its mere possibility” (Yu 2007, 8). Citing MacIntyre’s suggestion that mutual understanding becomes possible for adherents of rival systems after they learn each other’s language, Yu gives us a hint where to look for resolving MacIntyre’s confusion: “In saying this, however, the problem is no longer about the possibility of comparison, but about how comparison should be done and what qualities a comparativist needs to possess in order to get the job done appropriately. These are very different issues” (Yu 2007, 7). While I agree with this particular claim of Yu, I cannot agree with the implications of his “no longer”, which suggests that questioning the very possibility of comparison was the initial intention of MacIntyre’s article and only Yu’s interpretation clears up MacIntyre’s position saving him from confusion. I see Yu Jiyuan here not as resolving MacIntyre’s “confusion”, but as clearing up his own misreading of MacIntyre’s position. Yu does not cite where MacIntyre claims that comparison is not possible or that such possibility is at the centre of MacIntyre’s enquiry. Yu claims that “what is at stake is the possibility of comparison” (Yu 2007, 7), but the article of MacIntyre holds no such claim. On the contrary, as MacIntyre says Brought to you by | LMBA Lithuanian Research Library Consortium Authenticated Download Date | 4/28/17 1:17 PM 78 International Journal of Area Studies 8:1, 2013 straightforwardly at the end of the article, his whole undertaking was to discuss and to “bring out … more generally something of how conversation between rival bodies of theory and practice, rooted in very different cultures, has to proceed, if its interchanges are not to be sterile” (MacIntyre 1991, 120-1). Instead of arguing for (or against) the impossibility of comparison, MacIntyre was suggesting how we should compare and what an adequate and fruitful comparison is. As cited before, MacIntyre stressed the necessity that “we do not allow ourselves to forget that in comparing two fundamental standpoints at odds with each other … we have no neutral, independent standpoint from which to do so”, which simply means that “we may compare Confucianism and Aristotelianism from a Confucian standpoint, or from an Aristotelian” (MacIntyre 1991, 121; emphasis added). Thus, it seems to me, MacIntyre’s position, in this particular article at least, was all along not about possibility of comparison, but, in Yu Jiyuan’s words, about how comparison should be done7. If the main target of criticism of MacIntyre’s incommensurability thesis for Yu Jiyuan was the alleged negation of the possibility of comparison, so for May Sim, who devotes the whole chapter in her book as a direct response to MacIntyre, it is the alleged negation of the mutual understanding and possibility of a dialogue. May Sim undertakes an attempt to show that Confucius employs ten categories of Aristotle, even without explicitly mentioning them, because “to show how these thinkers share a fundamental set of categories is also to show that there are grounds for a kind of commensurability and hence for the possibility of dialogue” (Sim 2007, 50)8. May Sim further charges MacIntyre as maintaining that Confucianism and Aristotelianism “necessarily fail even to recognize the other’s problems and moral shortcomings” (Sim 2007, 70). She concludes that “even supposing these two ethical systems do not share all standards and measures, it does not follow that they are so radically disparate that they employ no kindred concepts or must necessarily find utterly unintelligible what the other advocates or repudiates” (Sim 2007, 70). In my earlier exposition I have showed in some length how MacIntyre made clear that mutual understanding between the rival parties is not precluded (MacIntyre 1991, 111). It is hard to see where May Sim finds MacIntyre’s claims about “utterly unintelligible” positions of rival systems, when he is, in actuality, advocating for the possibility of the adherents of different cultures to learn each other’s language “as a second first language” (MacIntyre 1991, 111). And not only does MacIntyre, contrary to May Sim’s claim, not suggest that the rival systems necessarily fail to see each other’s problems, he is instead arguing for the possibility that those outside of a certain standpoint may recognize failures of it “even when it has gone unacknowledged by the adherents of the tradition of inquiry which has failed” (MacIntyre 1991, 118). The main source of these misunderstandings, in my opinion, is the tendency to take MacIntyre’s claims as absolute when in reality they are not without Brought to you by | LMBA Lithuanian Research Library Consortium Authenticated Download Date | 4/28/17 1:17 PM VYTIS SILIUS. Neo-Aristotelian Confucianism? 79 important qualifications. For example, where MacIntyre says that he sees no “neutral and independent method of characterizing those materials in a way sufficient to provide the type of adjudication between competing theories of the virtues which I had once hoped to provide” (MacIntyre 1991, 105; emphasis added), for his critics it is simply a claim about “impossibility of adjudicating [the] rival claims” (Yu 2007, 7). Where MacIntyre stresses that the incommensurability is a relationship “over a certain period of time” and that “two different and rival conceptual schemes may be incommensurable at one stage of their development and yet become commensurable at another” (MacIntyre 1991, 109), for Yu it stands out as problem, “if two incommensurable systems can reach mutual understanding, why are they still incommensurable?” (Yu 2007, 9). It is important to point out that here the language, in which MacIntyre formulates his critique, may make his position seem ambiguous. The “incommensurability” is a strong term that precludes variations in degree, thus making it difficult to conceptualize what a “lesser” incommensurability between two systems would look like. If there are no intermediate states of “lesser” incommensurability that would eventually lead to dissolution of incommensurable states, can we – and this is Yu’s point – make sense out of the notion of “temporarily incommensurable” systems9? This view of incommensurability is correct, as Kuhn was also talking about “transition between incommensurables” that “must occur all at once (though not necessarily in an instant) or not at all” (Kuhn 1970, 150). However, the impossibility of change in degree of some state does not preclude possibility of change of the state itself. No-one can be “more” married today than one was yesterday, but one can certainly be married or not-married at different points of time. Further, Yu Jiyuan claims that “one cannot deny the possibility of comparative philosophy on the basis that different traditions have different psychologies, sociologies, and conceptual schemes” (Yu 2007, 8). This reference most probably is a reaction to MacIntyre’s claim that “every major theory of the virtues has internal to it, to some significant degree, its own philosophical psychology and its own philosophical politics and sociology” (MacIntyre 1991, 105). However in this paragraph MacIntyre, contrary to Yu’s claims, is not denying the possibility of comparative philosophy. He points out that various different areas of inquiry into human affairs are so interwoven that any account rich enough to be relevant for evaluation, for example, of theoretical claims about virtues, will already presuppose “one such theoretical stance regarding the virtues, rather than its rivals” (MacIntyre 1991, 105). As contemporary Chinese philosopher Wan Junren notes in his article on Confucian and Aristotelian ethics, “different definitions of the conception of the virtuous person (the bearer of virtue) create a difference in explanatory context” (Wan 2004, 124). Therefore, MacIntyre concludes, “there is just no neutral and independent method of characterizing those materials” (MacIntyre 1991, 105). Brought to you by | LMBA Lithuanian Research Library Consortium Authenticated Download Date | 4/28/17 1:17 PM

Description:
texts as a form of virtue ethics with its roots in Aristotle's thought and its However, in a volume dedicated to comparative studies Alasdair MacIntyre.
See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.