ebook img

Lifting Commutation Relations in Cuntz Algebras PDF

0.21 MB·English
Save to my drive
Quick download
Download
Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.

Preview Lifting Commutation Relations in Cuntz Algebras

LIFTING COMMUTATION RELATIONS IN CUNTZ ALGEBRAS 5 BRUCEBLACKADAR 1 0 2 t c O Abstract. Weexaminesplittingofthequotientmapfromthefullfreeprod- uctA∗B,ortheunitalfreeproductA∗CB,tothe(maximal)tensorproduct 3 A⊗B, forunital C*-algebras A andB. Such a splittingisvery rare,but we 1 showthereisoneifAandB areboththeCuntzalgebraO2 orO∞,andina fewothercases. Thesplittingisnotexplicit(andinprincipleprobablycannot ] be). WealsodescribesevereK-theoreticobstructions toasplitting. A O . h 1. Introduction t a m Lifting commutation relations from quotients of C*-algebras is a difficult and often unsolvable problem. We consider the essentially generic case where A and B [ are C*-algebras(to avoidunnecessary technicalities, we will only consider the case 3 ofunital AandB), andwehavethe quotientmapfromthe fullfree productorfull v unital free product to the tensor product. 3 8 Recall that the full free product A∗B is the universal C*-algebra generated by 1 copies of A and B with no relations (note that this free product is nonunital even 3 if A and B are unital), the unital free product A∗CB is the universal C*-algebra 0 generatedbycopiesofAandB withacommonunit,andthetensorproductA⊗B . 1 is the universal C*-algebra generated by commuting copies of A and B with a 0 common unit (all tensor products in this paper are maximal; our examples are 5 nuclear, so this is not much of an issue). There is a natural quotient map π from 1 : thefull freeproductA∗B, ortheunitalfreeproductA∗CB, tothe tensorproduct v A⊗B. i X We consider the question of whether there is a splitting (cross section) for this r quotient map, i.e. a *-homomorphism σ : A ⊗ B → A ∗ B (or to A ∗C B, not a necessarily unital) with π◦σ the identity on A⊗B. The short answer is “rarely”. Existence of a splitting for the quotient map from A∗B to A⊗B is equivalent to having a functorial procedure for beginning with two (not necessarily unital) *-homomorphismsφ:A→D and ψ :B →D of A and B into a C*-algebraD and manufacturing new *-homomorphisms φ˜: A → D and ψ˜: B → D such that φ˜(A) and φ˜(B) commute and have a common unit. “Functorial” means: (i) If f :D →D′ is a *-homomorphism, then f]◦φ=f ◦φ˜and f]◦ψ =f ◦ψ˜. (ii) If φ(A) and ψ(B) already commute and have a common unit, then φ˜= φ and ψ˜=ψ. Date:October 14,2015. 1 2 BRUCEBLACKADAR [Suchφandψdefinea*-homomorphismφ∗ψfromA∗BtoD;letφ˜andψ˜bedefined by (φ∗ψ)◦σ for a splitting σ]. Sucha functorialprocedureis automatically point- norm continuous in the sense that if φ :A→D and ψ :B →D converge point- n n norm to φ and ψ respectively, then φ˜ → φ˜ and ψ˜ → ψ˜ point-norm respectively n n [it suffices to note that φ ∗ψ →φ∗ψ point-norm]. n n Existence of a splitting is also equivalent to being able to always solve the fol- lowing lifting problem: given a C*-algebra D, a (closed) ideal J of D, and *- homomorphisms φ¯: A → D/J and ψ¯ : B → D/J such that φ¯(A) and ψ¯(B) com- mute and have a common unit, and φ¯ and ψ¯ separately lift to *-homomorphisms φ : A → D and ψ : B → D, find lifts φ˜ : A → D and ψ˜ : B → D such that φ˜(A) and φ˜(B) commute and have a common unit. We now give examples suggesting that splittings are “rare”. Example1.1. ConsiderthesimplestnontrivialC*-algebraC2. Thereisanexplicit description of C2∗CC2, which is the universal unital C*-algebra generated by two projections,asthe continuousfunctionsfrom[0,1]to M whicharediagonalatthe 2 endpoints(cf.[Bla06,IV.1.4.2]). Fromthisdescriptionitiseasytoseethatthereis nosplittingforthequotientmapfromC2∗CC2 toC2⊗C2 (whichisjustevaluation attheendpointsof[0,1]). Thereisa fortiorinosplittingforthequotientmapfrom C2∗C2 to C2⊗C2, since this quotient map factors through C2∗CC2. There is also no splitting for the quotient map from C2∗C2 to C2∗CC2 (4.1). Example 1.2. Hereis aneasierexample. Letn>1. Then the quotientmapfrom Mn∗CMn toMn⊗Mn cannotsplit(unitally). ForMn∗CMn hasMn asaquotient, but there is no nonzero homomorphismfrom Mn⊗Mn ∼=Mn2 to Mn. (Actually it cannot split nonunitally either; cf. Theorem 3.10, §4.) Similarly, if m and n (>1) are not relatively prime, there is no splitting for the quotient map from Mm ∗C Mn to Mm ⊗Mn ∼= Mmn, since Mm ∗CMn has Mp as a quotient, where p is the least common multiple of m and n, and p < mn. If m andn arerelativelyprime,the questionis moredelicate,but itseems unlikelythat Mm∗CMn contains a unital copy of Mmn (there is no such copy if either m or n is prime [RV98]). These obstructions to a splitting are K-theoretic; see section 3 for a discussion. Thereissomewhatmorehope ingeneralofgettingasplitting ifthe freeproduct is replaced by a “soft tensor product” A⊛ B where the copies of A and B are ǫ required to approximately commute (there are various ways to make this precise; cf.2.1). InthecaseofC2⊗C2,wewanttorestricttothecasewherethecommutator pq−qp of the two generating projections has small norm, say ≤ ǫ for a specified ǫ > 0. In fact, in this case, as soon as ǫ < 1 there is a splitting, as is easily seen. 2 A similar result holds for M ⊛ M , where the matrix units of the two matrix m ǫ n algebrasǫ-commute,andmoregenerallyforA⊛ B forAandB finite-dimensional, ǫ for small enough ǫ. But in only slightly more general settings there is no splitting even in the soft tensor product case: Example 1.3. If weregardC(T)⊗C(T) asthe universalC*-algebrageneratedby twocommutingunitaries,andweletC(T)⊛ C(T)bethe“softtorus,”theuniversal ǫ C*-algebrageneratedbytwounitariesuandvwithkuv−vuk≤ǫ([Exe93],[EEL91], [EE02]), then there is no splitting for the naturalquotientmapfromC(T)⊛ C(T) ǫ LIFTING COMMUTATION RELATIONS 3 to C(T)⊗C(T) for any ǫ > 0 (the Voiculescu matrices ([Voi83], [EL89]) can be used to show this is impossible). Thus a fortiori there can be no splitting for the quotient map from C(T)∗CC(T) to C(T)⊗C(T), since this quotient map factors throughC(T)⊛ C(T). Thisexamplecanbeessentiallysummarizedbysayingthat ǫ C(T2)∼=C(T)⊗C(T) is not semiprojective (2.3). Example 1.4. Not all obstructions to a splitting are K-theoretic. For example, there is no splitting for the quotient map from C([0,1])⊛ C([0,1]) to C([0,1])⊗ ǫ C([0,1])∼= C([0,1]2) for any ǫ > 0 since C([0,1]2) is not semiprojective (2.3), and hence no splitting for C([0,1])∗CC([0,1])→C([0,1])⊗C([0,1]) eventhoughthere is a splitting onthe K-theorylevel. (There is, however,a splitting for the quotient mapfromC([0,1])∗C([0,1])toC([0,1])∗CC([0,1]);infact,thereisasimpleexplicit cross section for the map from A∗C([0,1]) to A∗CC([0,1]) for any unital A.) One can ask whether the quotient map from A∗C B to A⊗B ever splits (if neither A nor B is C). Perhaps surprisingly,the answer is yes: it splits if A and B are certain Kirchberg algebras (but far from all pairs of Kirchberg algebras). For example,inoneofourmainresultsweshow(Corollary5.8)itsplitsifA=B =O 2 or if A is any semiprojective Kirchberg algebra and B = O∞. In fact, even the quotient map from A∗B to A⊗B splits in these cases. It has been known that in each of these cases, the quotient map from A⊛ B to A⊗B splits if ǫ > 0 ǫ is sufficiently small, where A⊛ B denotes the universal C*-algebra in which the ǫ standardgeneratorsandtheiradjointsinthetwoalgebrasǫ-commute(thisiseasily provedfrom the definition of semiprojectivity, cf. 2.3); but it came as a surprise to the author that there is a splitting even when no commutation condition (or any other relation) between the algebras is assumed. SeeSection2fordefinitionsandabriefdiscussionofsemiprojectivityandKirch- berg algebras, and [Bla06] for general information about C*-algebras. [Lor97] contains an extensive discussion of lifting problems and semiprojectivity for C*- algebras. Iamindebtedtotherefereeforpointingoutagapinthe proofofTheorem3.10, and for comments leading to Theorem 5.2 and an improvement in Theorem 5.3. I also thank Mikael Rørdam and Wilhelm Winter for helpful conversations. 2. Preliminaries 2.1. If A and B are separable and unital, and G and H are sets of generators for A and B respectively which are finite or sequences converging to 0, and ǫ > 0, we define A⊛ B to be the universal unital C*-algebra generated by unital copies of ǫ A and B such that k[a,b]k≤ ǫ for all a ∈G, b ∈ H. The notation does not reflect thedependence onG andH,whichisnottooimportantqualitatively;ifweinstead write A⊛ǫ,G,HB, and G′ and H′ are different sequences of generators converging to 0, then for any ǫ>0 there is an ǫ′ >0 such that the natural quotient map from A⊛ǫ,G,HB to A⊗B factors through A⊛ǫ′,G′,H′ B. We will thus fix G and H and just write A⊛ B. ǫ The natural quotient map from A⊛ǫ B to A⊗B factors through A⊛ǫ′ B for any ǫ′ <ǫ. 2.2. Recall the definition of semiprojectivity ([Bla85], [Bla06, II.8.3.7]): A separa- bleC*-algebraAissemiprojectiveif,wheneverDisaC*-algebra,(J )anincreasing n 4 BRUCEBLACKADAR sequence of closed (two-sided) ideals of D, and J = [∪J ]−, then any homomor- n phism φ: A→D/J can be partially lifted to a homomorphism ψ :A→D/J for n some sufficiently large n. IfAisunital,thenincheckingsemiprojectivityfromthedefinitionD andφmay be chosen unital, and then the partial lift ψ can be required to be unital (in fact, ψ will automatically become unital if n is sufficiently increased). There aremany knownexamples ofsemiprojectiveC*-algebras,but semiprojec- tivity is quite restrictive. For example, if X is a compact metrizable space, C(X) is semiprojective if and only if X is an ANR of dimension ≤ 1 [ST12]; the dimen- sionrestrictionis essentiallyexactlythe factthatcommutationrelationscannotbe partially lifted in general. See also 2.5. Proposition 2.3. Let A and B be unital semiprojective C*-algebras. Then the quotient map from A⊛ B to A⊗B splits (unitally) for some ǫ>0 (hence for all ǫ sufficiently small ǫ>0) if and only if A⊗B is semiprojective. Proof. Suppose A⊗B is semiprojective. Set D =A∗CB and Jn the kernel of the natural quotient map from D onto A⊛ B. Then (J ) is an increasing sequence 1/n n of closed ideals of D, and if J =[∪ J ]−, then D/J ∼=A⊗B. By semiprojectivity n n there is a (unital) partial lift of the identity map on A⊗B for some n. Conversely, suppose there is a splitting σ for the quotient map from A⊛ B to ǫ A⊗B for some ǫ > 0. Let D, (J ), φ be as in the definition of semiprojectivity, n with D and φ unital. For some sufficiently large n there are unital partial lifts ψ A of φ|A⊗1 and ψB of φ|1⊗B, which give a unital homomorphism ψ from A∗CB to D/Jn which is a lift of φ◦π, where π is the quotient map from A∗CB to A⊗B (this is essentially the argument that shows that A∗CB is semiprojective). Since the partial lifts of the generators of A and B asymptotically commute as n → ∞, if n is sufficiently increased, the map ψ factors through A⊛ B. Then ψ◦σ is a ǫ partial lift of φ, so A⊗B is semiprojective. (cid:3) 2.4. A Kirchberg algebra is a separable nuclear purely infinite (simple unital) C*- algebra. ItisnotknownwhethersuchaC*-algebraisautomaticallyinthebootstrap class for the Universal Coefficient Theorem [Bla98, 22.3.4]; a Kirchberg algebra in this bootstrap class is called a UCT Kirchberg algebra. The first Kirchberg algebras to be studied were the Cuntz algebras O , 2 ≤ n n ≤ ∞. If 2 ≤ n < ∞, O is the universal (unital) C*-algebra generated by n n isometries with mutually orthogonal range projections adding up to the identity. O∞ is the universal(unital) C*-algebrageneratedby a sequence of isometrieswith mutually orthogonal range projections. The next class was the (simple) Cuntz- Krieger algebras O . These are all UCT Kirchberg algebras. A Kirchberg (in part done also independently by Phillips) showed that the UCT Kirchberg algebras are classified by their K-theory. If A is a unital C*-algebra, write L(A) for the triple (K (A),K (A),[1 ]); L(A) is partof the Elliott invariant 0 1 A of A, and is the entire Elliott invariant of A if A is a Kirchberg algebra. A unital *-homomorphism φ from A to B induces a morphism from L(A) to L(B), i.e. a homomorphismφ∗0 :K0(A)→K0(B) with φ∗0([1A])=[1B] and a homomorphism φ∗1 : K1(A) → K1(B). The following facts are known (see [Rør02] for a good exposition): (i) If A and B are UCT Kirchberg algebras and α : L(A) → L(B) is a mor- phism, then there is a unital *-homomorphism φ: A→B with φ∗ =α. If LIFTING COMMUTATION RELATIONS 5 α is an isomorphism, φ can be chosen to be an isomorphism. In particu- lar, L(A) is a complete isomorphisminvariantof A among UCT Kirchberg algebras. (ii) If G and G are any countable abelian groups (recall that the K-groups 0 1 of any separable C*-algebra are countable), and u is any element of G , 0 then thereis a UCT KirchbergalgebraA(unique upto isomorphism)with L(A)∼=(G ,G ,u). 0 1 Cuntz showed that L(On) = (Zn−1,0,1) if n < ∞ and L(O∞) = (Z,0,1). As technical results toward the above classification, Kirchberg ([KP00]; cf. [Rør02]) showed the following facts about tensor products: (iii) For any Kirchberg algebra A (UCT or not), O ⊗A ∼= O . In particular, 2 2 O ⊗O ∼=O . 2 2 2 (iv) For any Kirchberg algebra A (UCT or not), O∞⊗A ∼= A. In particular, O∞⊗O∞ ∼=O∞. (v) The infinite tensor products O2∞ and O∞∞ are isomorphic to O2 and O∞ respectively. The isomorphism O ⊗O ∼= O (which was first shown by Elliott; cf. [Rør94]) 2 2 2 and the others are quite deep results. They are highly nonconstructive; in fact, it isinprincipleessentiallyimpossibletogiveanexplicitisomorphismofO ⊗O and 2 2 O by the results of [AC13]. 2 2.5. Ithasrecentlybeenshown[End15]thatifAisaUCTKirchbergalgebra,then A is semiprojective if and only if K∗(A) is finitely generated (in fact, this problem was the original motivation for the work of the present paper). Special cases were previously known: it is easy to show that O (n<∞) and, more generally, O for n A any A is semiprojective [Bla85]. O∞ was shown to be semiprojective in [Bla04], and more general results were obtained in [Szy02] and [Spi09]. 3. K-Theoretic Obstructions, Unital Free Product Case It turns out that there are rather severe K-theoretic obstructions to a splitting for the quotient map from A ∗C B to A ⊗ B. In this section, we will restrict attentiontoseparablenuclearC*-algebrasinthe UCTclass[Bla98, 22.3.4],sothat theKu¨nnethTheoremforTensorProducts[Bla98,23.1.3]andtheresultsof[Ger97] hold, although some of what we do here works in greater generality. The analysis is largely an elementary (but moderately complicated) exercise in group theory, so some details are omitted. Let A and B be unital C*-algebras of the above form. We recall the results of the Ku¨nneth theorem and of [Ger97]: K0(A⊗B)∼=[K0(A)⊗ZK0(B)]⊕[K1(A)⊗ZK1(B)]⊕TorZ1(K0(A),K1(B))⊕TorZ1(K1(A),K0(B)) K1(A⊗B)∼=[K0(A)⊗ZK1(B)]⊕[K1(A)⊗ZK0(B)]⊕TorZ1(K0(A),K0(B))⊕TorZ1(K1(A),K1(B)) Z where Tor denotes the Tor-functor of homological algebra. 1 From the exact sequence of [Ger97], we obtain: K (A∗B)∼=K (A)⊕K (B) 0 0 0 K (A∗B)∼=K (A)⊕K (B) 1 1 1 6 BRUCEBLACKADAR K0(A∗CB)∼=[K0(A)⊕K0(B)]/h([1A],−[1B])i K1(A∗CB)∼=K1(A)⊕K1(B)⊕Z if [1 ] and [1 ] are torsion elements of K (A) and K (B) respectively, and A B 0 0 K1(A∗CB)∼=K1(A)⊕K1(B) otherwise. In K1(A∗CB), the first two summands are well defined as subsets of the group, but the extra Z summand is not. The quotient map from A∗B to A∗C B induces the obvious maps on the K- groups. The quotient map π from A∗CB to A⊗B induces the following maps: on K0, π∗0(x,y)=x⊗[1B]+[1A]⊗y in the K0(A)⊗ZK0(B) summand; on the first two summands of K1, π∗1(x,y) = ([1A]⊗y)⊕(x⊗[1B]) in the [K0(A)⊗Z K1(B)]⊕ [K1(A)⊗ZK0(B)] summands. If there is a splitting, there must be crosssections for these maps. There will be a K-theoretic obstruction almost any time both A and B have nontrivial K , or if 1 the rank of K of both A and B is at least 2. 0 We first dispose of the extra summand of Z in K when it occurs. One can give 1 a more precise and detailed analysis of this summand, but the following argument suffices for the purposes of this paper. Lemma 3.1. If [1A] and [1B] are torsion, the extrasummand Z in K1(A∗CB) can be chosen so that the restriction φ of the quotient map to this summand maps into Z Tor (K (A),K (B)). 1 0 0 Proof. Suppose m[1 ] = 0 in K (A) and n[1 ] = 0 in K (B) for natural numbers A 0 B 0 m,n. Sincethe exactsequenceof[Ger97]isnatural(functorial),itdoesnotchange if we replace A and B by A⊗O∞ and B ⊗O∞ respectively, i.e. we may assume A and B are properly infinite. Thus A and B contain unital copies of O and m+1 On+1 respectively. There is a corresponding summand of Z in K1(Om+1∗COn+1), which is well defined as the entire group K1(Om+1∗COn+1), and the Z summand in K1(A∗C B) can be taken to be the image of this summand, which maps into TorZ(K (O ),K (O )) since this is all of K (O ⊗O ). (cid:3) 1 0 m+1 0 n+1 1 m+1 n+1 Corollary 3.2. There can be a splitting at the K-theory level only if φ is zero, i.e. the image of K1(A∗CB) in K1(A⊗B) is the same as the image of the subgroup K (A)⊕K (B). 1 1 Z Proof. Tor (K (A),K (B))isatorsiongroup,soφcannotbeinjective. Aquotient 1 0 0 map of Z can only split if it is zero or injective. (cid:3) Thus we are reduced to considering only the summands K (A) ⊕ K (B) of 1 1 K1(A∗CB). Proposition 3.3. A splitting for the quotient map from A∗CB to A⊗B is im- possible under any of the following conditions: (i) K1(A)⊗ZK1(B)6=0. (ii) (rank(K (A)))(rank(K (B))) > rank(K (A)) + rank(K (B)), or 0 0 0 0 rank(K (A))+rank(K (B))−1 if [1 ] or [1 ] has infinite order. 0 0 A B LIFTING COMMUTATION RELATIONS 7 Z (iii) Tor1(K∗(A),K∗(B))6=0. This is only the beginning of the K-theoretic obstructions. We will analyze the case where K∗(A) and K∗(B) are finitely generated. Then we have K (A)=Za⊕G , K (A)=Zn⊕G 0 0 1 1 K (B)=Zb⊕H , K (B)=Zm⊕H 0 0 1 1 for nonnegative integers a,b,n,m and finite abelian groups G ,G ,H ,H . 0 1 0 1 In order to have a splitting, from 3.3(iii) we need the ordersof G and G to be 0 1 relatively prime to the orders of H and H , so we will assume this from now on. 0 1 We also havethatK1(A)⊗ZK1(B)=0 is necessaryfor a splitting by 3.3(i), which impliesthatnandmcannotbothbe nonzero;withoutlossofgeneralityweassume m = 0. We must have Zn⊗ZH1 ∼= H1n = 0, so either n = 0 or H1 = 0. We then obtain: (1) K0(A∗CB)=(Za+b⊕G0⊕H0)/h[1A],−[1B]i (2) K (A⊗B)=Zab⊕Gb ⊕Ha 0 0 0 (3) K1(A∗CB)=Zn⊕G1⊕H1 (4) K (A⊗B)=Znb⊕Gb ⊕Ha⊕Hn 1 1 1 0 since Gi⊗ZHj =0 for all i,j. We need for the induced maps from Ki(A∗CB) to Ki(A⊗B) to be surjective and have a cross section. For this, we need Hn =0, so n=0 or H =0. 0 0 3.4. There are two trivial cases: K∗(A) is either (0,0), or (Z,0) and [1A] = 1, in whichcasethereisnorestrictiononK∗(B). (Thesituationis,ofcourse,symmetric in A and B.) 3.5. Next we can easily dispose of the case where n>0. In this case we observed earlier that H0 = H1 = 0, and from (4) we see that b ≤ 1. Thus K∗(B) is either (0,0) or (Z,0). Suppose K0(B) = Z. The map π∗1 from K1(A∗C B) ∼= Zn⊕G1 to K (A⊗B)∼=Z⊕G is multiplication by [1 ]; for this to be surjective, we need 1 1 B for [1 ] to be a generator of K (B). Thus we are in one of the trivial cases. B 0 3.6. From now on we assume n=0, i.e. K (A) and K (B) are finite groups. The 1 1 situation is now symmetric in A and B. The map from K0(A∗CB) to K0(A⊗B) must send Za+b/h[1 ],−[1 ]i onto Zab, and thus we must have ab ≤ a+b, and if A B either the torsion-free part of [1 ] or [1 ] is nonzero, we must have ab≤a+b−1. A B Thus we have that either a or b is ≤ 1, or a = b = 2 and the torsion-free part of both[1A]and[1B]is0. Butinthe casea=b=2,the mapsπ∗0 onthe torsion-free partofK arezeroandcannotbesurjective. Thusthereisnosplittinginthiscase. 0 3.7. Nowassumewithoutlossofgeneralitythata=0 or1. We firstdisposeofthe cases where [1 ] or [1 ] has finite order (which includes the case a=0). Suppose A B (K (A),K (A),[1 ])=(Z⊕G ,G ,(u,r)) 0 1 A 0 1 (K (B),K (B),[1 ])=(Zb⊕H ,H ,(v,s)) 0 1 B 0 1 8 BRUCEBLACKADAR Then K∗(A∗CB)=((Z⊕G0⊕Zb⊕H0)/h(u,r,v,s)i,G1⊕H1) K∗(A⊗B)=(Zb⊕Gb0⊕H0,Gb1⊕H1) Ifu=0, thenπ∗0 maps Zb⊕H0 to 0, sofor the mapto be surjective wemust have b≤ 1 and H0 = 0; if b =1, for π∗0 to map Z⊕G0 onto K0(A⊗B) we must have v = 1. Similarly, π∗1 maps the H1 to 0, so H1 = 0. Thus we are in a trivial case (for B). If v = 0, we argue similarly that G = G = 0 and u = 1, so we are again in a 0 1 trivial case (for A). Now consider the case (K (A),K (A),[1 ])=(G ,G ,r) 0 1 A 0 1 (K (B),K (B),[1 ])=(Zb⊕H ,H ,(v,s)) 0 1 B 0 1 where b ≥ 1 and v = 0. Then as before G = G = 0 and we are in a trivial case 0 1 (for A). The last case is where both K∗(A) and K∗(B) are torsion (finite) groups. Then K∗(A⊗B)=(0,0) and there is no K-theoretic restriction. 3.8. The remaining case is where a = 1, b ≥ 1, and [1 ] and [1 ] have infinite A B order. This is the most delicate case. Write u and v for the components of [1 ] A and[1 ]inthetorsion-freepartsofK (A)andK (B)respectively;wemayassume B 0 0 without loss of generality that u>0 and that v =(w,0,...,0) with w >0. First consider the case b=1. We have K0(A∗CB)∼=(Z⊕G0⊕Z⊕H0)/h(u,r,−w,−s)i∼=Z2/h(u,−w)i⊕G0⊕H0 and the map π∗0 to K0(A ⊗ B) = Z ⊕ Gb0 ⊕ H0 must send Z2/h(u,−w)i onto the first coordinate. This map is multiplication by w on the first coordinate plus multiplication by u on the second; thus it can only be surjective if u and w are relatively prime. In this case, it is both injective and surjective on this piece. The map π∗0 maps the G0 to the G0 and is multiplication by w. For this to be surjective (hence bijective), we must have wG = G , i.e. w must be relatively 0 0 prime to the order of G . Similarly, u must be relatively prime to the order of H . 0 0 The same argument for π∗1 shows that u and w are relatively prime to the orders of H and G respectively. 1 1 We cannot rule out the case where u and v are greater than 1 and relatively prime. For example, consider the case u = 2, v = 3. For simplicity suppose the K-groups are torsion-free, i.e. K∗(A) = (Z,0,2) and K∗(B) = (Z,0,3). Then K0(A∗CB)=Z2/h(2,−3)i with order unit [(2,0)]=[(0,3)]. K0(A⊗B)=Z with orderunit 6,and the map π∗0 sends [(x,y)] to 3x+2y, andis an isomorphism;the inverse map sends n to [(n,−n)]. It is possible that this inverse map is induced by a homomorphism on the algebra level in some cases (e.g. possibly in the case A = M2(O∞) and B = M3(O∞)) (3.12), although it is not in the case A = M2, B =M (3.11). 3 Thus the possibilities are L(A)=(Z⊕G ,G ,(u,r)), L(B)=(Z⊕H ,H ,(w,s)) 0 1 0 1 whereuisrelativelyprimetow andtotheordersofH andH ,andw isrelatively 0 1 prime to the orders of G and G . 0 1 LIFTING COMMUTATION RELATIONS 9 3.9. Now consider the case b>1. We have K0(A∗CB)∼=(Z⊕G0⊕Zb⊕H0)/h(u,r,−w,0,...,0,−s)i ∼=Z2/h(u,−w)i⊕Zb−1⊕G ⊕H 0 0 and the map π∗0 to K0(A⊗ B) = Zb ⊕Gb0 ⊕ H0 must send Z2/h(u,−w)i onto the first coordinate. This map is multiplication by w on the first coordinate plus multiplication by u on the second; thus it can only be surjective if u and w are relatively prime. In this case, it is both injective and surjective on this piece. The map π∗0 sends G0 into Gb0 and sends x to (wx,0,...,0). This can only be surjective if G0 = 0. Similarly, π∗1 sends G1 into Gb1 by the same formula, so G1 =0. Thus K∗(A)=(Z,0). However, we do not need to have u = 1. But there is a restriction: the map π∗0 sends H0 into H0 by multiplication by u; this needs to be surjective, i.e. u is relatively prime to the order of H . Similarly, uH = H , so u is relatively prime 0 1 1 to the order of H . Thus, for any b>1, we have the possibilities 1 L(A)=(Z,0,u), L(B)=(Zb⊕H ,H ,(w,0,...,0,s)) 0 1 where u is relatively prime to w and to the orders of H and H . 0 1 We summarize: Theorem 3.10. Let A and B be separable nuclear unital C*-algebras in the UCT class withfinitely generatedK-theory. Then therecan bea splittingfor the quotient map from A∗CB to A⊗B only in the following situations: (i) L(A)=(0,0,0)or (Z,0,1), L(B)arbitrary (or vice versa). Inthefirstcase L(A⊗B)=(0,0,0), and in the second L(A⊗B)∼=L(B). (ii) L(A)=(G ,G ,r), L(B)=(H ,H ,s). In this case L(A⊗B)=(0,0,0). 0 1 0 1 (iii) L(A) = (Z⊕G ,G ,(u,r)), L(B) = (Z⊕H ,H ,(w,s)), where u is rela- 0 1 0 1 tively prime to w and to the orders of H and H , and w is relatively prime 0 1 to the orders of G and G . 0 1 (iv) L(A)=(Z,0,u), L(B)=(Zb⊕H ,H ,(w,0,...,0,s)), where b>1, and u 0 1 is relatively prime to w and to the orders of H and H . 0 1 In (ii)–(iv), G ,G ,H ,H are any finite abelian groups with the orders of G and 0 1 0 1 0 G relatively prime to the orders of H and H . 1 0 1 In all cases except (ii), K∗(A∗CB) is the same as K∗(A⊗B) and the maps π∗0 and π∗1 are isomorphisms. In case (ii), we have L(A∗CB)=((G0/rG0)⊕(H0/sH0),G1⊕H1,0) i.e. the identity always has class 0. Theorem 3.10 does not guarantee a splitting in these cases; there often is not. For one thing, there may be more obstructions coming from ordered K-theory: Example 3.11. (cf. Example 1.2) Suppose K∗(A) = K∗(B) = (Z,0) but [1A] = m, [1B] = n with m,n > 1. Then K∗(A ⊗ B) ∼= (Z,0) and K∗(A ∗C B) ∼= (Z2/h(m,−n)i,0), so there is potentially a splitting on the group level. But de- pending on the actual map π∗ there may not be one at the scaled ordered group level, or even at the group level. Supposen=m. ThenK0(A∗CB)∼=Z⊕Zn,andtheorderunitinK0(A∗CB)is (n,0). TheorderunitinK0(A⊗B)isn2. Themapπ∗ :K0(A∗CB)→K0(A⊗B)is 10 BRUCEBLACKADAR multiplication by n, which is not surjective, so there canbe no crosssection. More generally, in n and m are not relatively prime, and d is their greatest common divisor and p is their least common multiple, then K0(A∗CB) ∼= Z⊕Zd and the order unit in K0(A ∗C B) is (p,0). The order unit in K0(A ⊗ B) is mn; π∗ is multiplication by mn =d and is not surjective. p Inthesecasesthereisnotasplittingatthegrouplevel. Butsupposemandnare relativelyprime. Thenthereisasplittingatthegrouplevel(π∗ isanisomorphism). ButthepositiveconeinK (A⊗B)canbelargerthanthepositiveconeintheunital 0 freeproductK0(A∗CB),forexampleifA=Mm,B =Mn;inthiscasethepositive coneinK (A⊗B)∼=Zistheusualone,butitisshownin[RV98]that(atleastifm 0 or n is prime) the positive cone in K0(A∗CB) is the subsemigroup of Z generated by m and n. Example3.12. ThesituationcanbenicerwithKirchbergalgebras: theunitalfree product M2(O∞)∗CM3(O∞) contains a unital copy of M6. Let {eij :1≤i,j ≤3} be the standard matrix units in the M3(O∞). There are mutually orthogonal subprojectionsf1,f2,f3,g1,g2ofe11inM3(O∞)addinguptoe11suchthatf1,f2,f3 areequivalenttoe andg andg areequivalent(take[f ]=[e ]and[g ]=−[e ] 11 1 2 k 11 k 11 for all k in K0(O∞)∼=Z). Then f +f +f ∼1 . 1 2 3 M3(O∞) We have that 1 =1 since the free product is unital, and 1 is M3(O∞) M2(O∞) M2(O∞) the sum of two equivalent projections in the M2(O∞), so f1+f2+f3 is the sum of two equivalent projections r ,r . Set p = r +g and p = r +g ; then 1 2 11 1 1 12 2 2 e =p +p ,andp ∼p . Forj =2,3setp =e p e andp =e p e ; 11 11 12 11 12 j1 j1 11 1j j2 j1 12 1j then {p :1≤j ≤3,1≤k≤2} jk are six mutually orthogonal equivalent projections in M2(O∞)∗CM3(O∞) adding up to the identity. This argument generalizes to show that if m and n are relatively prime, then Mm(O∞)∗CMn(O∞)containsa unitalcopyofMmn. Thus thereis no K-theoretic obstruction to a splitting in this case. Example 3.13. IfAorB doesnothavefinitely generatedK-theory,the situation can be much more complicated. For example, if A is the CAR algebra, there does not appear to be any K-theoretic obstruction to a cross section for the quotient map from A∗CA to A⊗A, but it is questionable that there is a splitting in this case. One unresolved question is: if there is a splitting for the quotient map from A∗C B to A⊗B, is there necessarily a unital splitting (and is a splitting even necessarilyunital)? It follows fromTheorem3.10and the comment afterwardthat in the UCT case with finitely generated K-theory, any splitting must necessarily at least send the identity of A⊗B to a projection in A∗CB whose K0-class is the same as the K -class of the identity. 0 4. K-Theoretic Obstructions, General Free Product Case We can do an essentially identical analysis of obstructions to splitting of the quotient map from A∗B to A⊗B. But this case can also be handled more easily: ifthereisasplittingforthismap,thereisalsoasplittingforthequotientmapfrom

See more

The list of books you might like

Most books are stored in the elastic cloud where traffic is expensive. For this reason, we have a limit on daily download.