Marxism and anarchism in an age of neoliberal crisis Simon Choat School of Economics, History, and Politics, Kingston University, Penrhyn Road, Kingston upon Thames, Surrey KT1 2EE Abstract In the aftermath of the financial crisis that began in 2008, various commentators have suggested that we are witnessing an ‘anarchist turn’: a revival of anarchist ideas and strategies exemplified by resistance movements such as Occupy. In the light of this revival, some have argued in favour of a ‘left convergence’: an alliance between anarchism and Marxism that can unite the radical left. Although it accepts that such alliances can have pragmatic efficacy, this article argues that these calls for convergence should be treated with caution. It challenges claims of a recent anarchist turn by claiming that neoliberalism itself has been the central beneficiary of a crisis to which the left has failed to respond effectively. Given this context of reversal and even defeat for the left, the article suggests that what is required today is a sober reflection on the relative merits of Marxism and anarchism. It sets out to establish what distinguishes Marxism from anarchism today and it argues that the former contains superior resources with which to challenge the current dominance of neoliberalism. In order to elucidate the strengths of Marxism, it addresses three common anarchist criticisms of Marxism concerning: its authoritarian strategies; its economic reductionism; and its lack of moral or ethical perspective. It argues that each of these criticisms inadvertently highlight the advantages of Marxism over anarchism. The aim of the article is not render anarchism obsolete but to respond to claims of an anarchist turn and subsequent calls for left convergence by highlighting the continuing vitality and strength of Marxism and raising questions for those who advocate an anarchist politics. * * * 1 Introduction: A left convergence? In the wake of the financial crisis that began in 2007, there have been a growing number of calls for convergence on the radical left. In particular, there have been appeals for a rapprochement or alliance between anarchism and Marxism (e.g. Kinna and Prichard 2012). These calls have a certain logic, given that both anarchism and Marxism appear especially well placed to address the neoliberal conditions that led to the crisis. The consequences of neoliberal globalisation have after all vindicated some of the central arguments of both ideologies: in The Communist Manifesto Marx and Engels presciently anticipated economic globalisation and its effects, while the dispersion of state sovereignty that it has produced has arguably validated claims that at least at a global level we already live in an anarchic world (Bottici 2013: 25). More importantly, both anarchism and Marxism have played high-‐ profile roles in responding to the crisis: anarchist activists, ideas, and strategies have been central to resistance movements like Occupy (Graeber 2012, 2013), while Marxist political economy has proved invaluable in analysing events over which mainstream classical economics has only been able to maintain an embarrassed silence (Lapavitsas 2012, 2013). On the other hand, however, it can be argued with equal plausibility that anarchism, Marxism, and the left in general have proved notably ineffective in responding to the crisis. Far from representing a revival, in Western Europe at least it is just as credible to claim that this is a moment of historic defeat for the left. If this has been a neoliberal crisis, it is not simply because it was caused by neoliberalism, nor because for a brief moment it seemed that the theories and logic of neoliberalism had been discredited and hence thrown into crisis. Rather, it is above all because neoliberal capitalism has emerged even stronger from the crisis that it caused: what is euphemistically named ‘austerity’ represents the 2 consolidation and extension of the same neoliberal policies that produced the very problems (of recession, debt, and unemployment) that it is purported to solve. So while in theory anarchism and Marxism are well placed to offer insights into our current predicament, in practice the conditions for any revival of the radical left are not necessarily propitious. As such, it is my argument that we should treat with caution calls for an alliance between anarchism and Marxism and instead engage in sober reflection on their relative strengths and weaknesses. Anarchists and Marxists find common cause in confronting the forms of exploitation and oppression generated by contemporary neoliberalism, and our everyday organisation and activism can only be strengthened by maintaining and extending existing alliances. But there is no contradiction in calling for solidarity in practice and using the tools of theory to investigate and sharpen distinctions. Indeed, any attempt to find ‘common ground’ must necessarily involve some assessment of the relative strengths and weaknesses of the two parties, as a prelude to the search for or negotiation of such common ground. Hence although I ultimately argue that Marxism offers superior resources for challenging neoliberalism, this claim does not in any way rule out a potential left convergence. Even those calling for convergence implicitly acknowledge that anarchism and Marxism remain distinct: this article sets out to explore those distinctions in more detail. Recognising that both anarchism and Marxism are broad and varied movements, I nonetheless claim that it is both possible and desirable to identify important differences between each. I will argue that the recent crisis and its aftermath help to bring into sharper focus the differences between anarchism and Marxism – and, moreover, illuminate the advantages of the latter over the former in terms of helping us to understand and resist the dominance of neoliberalism. 3 This argument is not made in the interests of doctrinal purity or petty political point-‐ scoring, but as part of a pragmatic investigation into the opportunities for resistance under current conditions. Moreover, rather than initiating a Marxist offensive against anarchism, my argument here is to a great extent reactive or defensive: it is made to counter and moderate claims that radical politics over the past decade has experienced an ‘anarchist turn’ (Critchley 2013), that we are witnessing a ‘new anarchism’ (Graeber 2007) or ‘neo-‐ anarchism’ (Castells 2005), or even that ‘we are all anarchists now’ (Carter and Morland 2004). Very often these celebratory claims are made at the expense of Marxism, as a resurgent and rejuvenated anarchism is contrasted with an outmoded and exhausted Marxism. What follows, therefore, is as much a defence of Marxism as it is a critique of anarchism. While it is indisputable that many radical activists today identify as anarchists, many do not, and I maintain that there are flaws in anarchist approaches to politics. In order to draw out the strengths of Marxism, I will address three of the most common criticisms of Marxism made by anarchists, and in so doing attempt to develop a definition of Marxism that is restrictive enough to distinguish it from anarchism yet capacious enough to incorporate its many varieties. Those criticisms are that, first, Marxism favours authoritarian forms of organisation, and that this authoritarianism is rooted in theoretical flaws. Secondly, that Marxism is economically reductive, unable in particular to account for the specific threats posed by the power of the state. Thirdly and finally, that Marxism lacks a moral theory and hence its economic critique requires an ethical supplement. I will argue that each of these criticisms unintentionally highlights the advantages of Marxism over anarchism. In making my argument I will respond to recent anarchist texts, avoiding as much as possible the disputes of the ‘classical’ period, such as those between Marx and Proudhon or Bakunin, or as took place around the 1917 4 revolution. This is for a number of reasons. First, those disputes are already well known enough and do not need to be rehearsed here.1 Second, while those disputes have enormous historical importance, and the terms in which they were undertaken remain influential, there is a danger that in focusing on them we obscure what is distinctive about and most relevant to contemporary radical politics, replicating yesterday’s polemics rather than illuminating today’s disagreements. Finally, anarchism is if anything much broader than Marxism, and hence any characterisation of anarchism and its critique of Marxism will necessarily be selective: focusing only on recent anarchist works is one, relatively uncontroversial, way of narrowing the criteria of definition. The presentations of Marxism and anarchism that follow will of course be open to dispute, but that is true of all attempts to determine any large, diverse, and living body of political thought and practice. Strategy and organisation The most common way to distinguish anarchism from Marxism is to claim that while they share a mutual aim – a stateless and classless society – they diverge in their proposed means to that end. Anarchists reject the consequentialist claim that the end justifies the means and instead insist on a prefigurative politics in which the means prefigure the end: because they look to a non-‐hierarchical and decentralised future, they support non-‐ hierarchical and decentralised strategies in the present (Franks 2012: 216, 220; Shannon et al 2012: 32; Schmidt and van der Walt 2009: 65). This difference is often framed in terms of strategy, as in the recent debate between the syndicalist anarchist Lucien van der Walt and the Marxist-‐Leninist Paul Blackledge, in which the issue of the state and the associated questions of political organisation and leadership came to the fore (Blackledge 2010; van 1 For an overview of Marx’s relationship to anarchism, see the classic study by Thomas 2010. 5 der Walt 2011; Blackledge 2011). In practice the anarchist position entails support for tactics such as direct action and the rejection of antidemocratic forms of organisation in favour of autonomous and polycentric networks of activists (Gordon 2008: 34-‐40, 14-‐17; Graeber 2007). Because the state is viewed as an authoritarian body, they reject any engagement with the state, from participation in parliamentary elections to the revolutionary seizure of the state apparatus. This is often formulated as a rejection of politics per se: political parties in particular are viewed as elitist, autocratic, and likely to lead to the reformist co-‐option of radical goals (Kinna 2009: 161). Marxism – especially in its Leninist forms – is in contrast viewed by anarchists as authoritarian in its promotion of a vanguard party and a dictatorship of the proletariat. The dangers of such an approach have for anarchists been confirmed by the experiences of Marxist regimes in the 20th century: ‘all Marxist regimes ended as state capitalist dictatorships’ (van der Walt 2011). For anarchists this is not merely a contingent dispute over choice of tactics, because they argue that the practical deficiencies in Marxism that they identify are rooted in theoretical weaknesses, two of which in particular are significant. First, by viewing the state merely as the instrument of the ruling class, Marxism does not recognise that the state is itself an autonomous source of power and so is always a threat to freedom, even if it is controlled by the working class or their representatives. Second, because it privileges a single site of oppression – i.e. capitalist relations of production – it also privileges a single agent of change, namely the industrial proletariat, who must necessarily be led by a vanguard leadership of intellectuals whose task is to interpret and analyse that oppression and who thereby disable the potential for bottom-‐up emancipation (Newman 2010: 81-‐86). 6 It can hardly be denied that some forms of Marxism have been violently and disastrously authoritarian in practice. But this historical fact does not indicate a fundamental flaw within Marxism. In the first place, and as some anarchists recognise (Franks 2012), Marxism is not inherently authoritarian and contemporary Marxism certainly cannot be reduced to Leninism.2 There is a diversity of tactics and organisational forms within both anarchism and Marxism: neither can be defined or condemned according to their practical strategies. Like anarchists, Marxists such as John Holloway (2010) and Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri (2006) have advocated ‘networked’ and ‘horizontal’ forms of organisation that reject or seek to limit centralised and ‘vertical’ hierarchies. The point here is not that all Marxists are in agreement with Holloway or Hardt and Negri, nor that they represent a more ‘authentic’ or compelling form of Marxism than Leninism: the point is simply that the anarchist critique of Marxism’s authoritarianism is called into question by the existence of self-‐identified Marxists who advocate explicitly non-‐authoritarian modes of organisation. Moreover, such figures are only the latest in a long-‐standing line of libertarian Marxists, from Luxemburg via Marcuse and Guérin and even including some of Lenin’s work (The State and Revolution was anti-‐authoritarian enough to be praised by Lenin’s anarchist contemporaries [Birchall 2010]). By invoking the threatening spectre of the dictatorship of the proletariat, anarchists are not only reviving debates whose relevance is doubtful when applied to our own political, economic, and social conditions, they are also failing to recognise or acknowledge the diversity of Marxism. Notwithstanding this strategic plurality within Marxism, it is anyway questionable whether a particular form of organisation can be defined as intrinsically progressive. Given 2 Though even where the existence of other traditions in Marxism is recognised by anarchists, the conclusion is often that ‘the predominant element’ of Marxism remains nonetheless ‘overwhelmingly authoritarian’ (Schmidt and van der Walt 2009: 24). 7 that both the US army and its enemies such as al-‐Qaeda, for example, are increasingly adopting polycentric, networked forms (albeit in combination with traditional vertical hierarchies), it is clear that such forms do not always produce a radical politics. Ultimately, what really distinguishes emancipatory from reactionary groups are not their strategies or organisational arrangements but the goals that they pursue (Hardt and Negri 2006: 54-‐62, 93, 218). The risk of anarchism’s preoccupation with prefigurative politics is that is fetishises tactical purity at the expense of political analysis and aims. Above all, the anarchist critique of Marxist strategies is premised on an overly simplistic understanding of the relationship between theory and practice. Anarchists have attempted to attribute Marxism’s supposed antidemocratic tactics to its theoretical claims, but there can never be any straightforward connection between theoretical arguments and organisational or strategic practices. The links between theory and practice are complex and subtle and it is dangerous to read back from the practical failures of a movement in order to criticise a set of concepts and theories. To claim, for example, that Stalinism can be explained by mistakes in Marx’s methodology, or even that the former throws doubt on the latter, is to risk the idealist and ultimately untenable argument that political or economic failures are produced by incorrect or adequate theory. Historical events can never simply disprove or discredit any ideological position, because ideas are always developed and applied within a variety of social and historical contexts. The gulag does not result from something that Marx wrote, but from a complex web of material causes. Anarchists in particular should be especially wary of attempting to discredit Marxism in this way, because practical experiments in anarchism have so seldom been successful: if we are to judge an ideology or movement by its operation ‘in practice’, then anarchism does not fare much better than Marxism (Choat 2013: 337-‐8). It may be that Leninist tactics have not achieved a 8 classless and stateless society, but so far neither have anarchist tactics: anarchists may have cleaner hands than Marxists, but that is only because anarchists have had their hands on so little. The anarchist critique of Marxist organisational forms is unconvincing, then, because it does not acknowledge the diversity of Marxist approaches and it tends towards a theoreticism that sees a linear, causal, and continuous line from theory to practice. Nonetheless, there are significant differences of strategy between anarchism and Marxism: it is just that these are less to do with organisation as such, and are much more broadly to do with differing attitudes toward politics and the state. Although some (though by no means all) anarchists have supported formal political organisations, with rules, membership criteria, and even internal discipline (Schmidt and van der Walt 2009: 247-‐263), they have traditionally rejected any engagement with the state – whether it be voting, demanding legal rights or protections, forming political parties, or attempting the revolutionary seizure of government – on the basis that such engagement can only end up replicating the oppressive hierarchies that they are fighting: either it will lead to new forms of dictatorship and bureaucracy (such as developed in the Soviet Union); or it will lead to parliamentary reformism and hence merely reinforce existing structures and relations of power. If Marxists support (qualified) engagement with the state and even the formation of political parties, however, it is not because they think that centralised hierarchies are desirable or inevitable, but because they begin from a different understanding of politics. They argue that the anarchist abstention from state politics denies us the most effective means of political action: we disempower ourselves rather than the state when we refuse to engage with it. Making demands on the state does not necessarily entail an endorsement of the state, any more than the demands that are made by employees during a strike are an 9 endorsement of the employer or of the system of wage-‐labour (Marx 1988). Anarchists themselves have at least implicitly recognised the efficacy of political engagement by occasionally supporting the policies of certain governments and even participating in elections (Engels 1988; Franks 2012: 216). More than this, abstention from state politics is not a genuine option: whether we like it or not, we are all already involved in state politics, because we are all always already submitted to state power, control, and oppression. Anarchists are concerned that participation in conventional politics will lead to parliamentary reformism. But this concern is itself ultimately premised on a tacit acceptance of the liberal-‐parliamentary understanding of politics: to claim that we can safely repudiate state politics simply by refusing ever to enter a polling booth is to assume that ‘the state’ stops at the door of Parliament. Marxists, in contrast, have argued that the state apparatus includes educational institutions, the media, churches, the family, and so on (e.g. Althusser 1971): simply in going about our daily lives we are all therefore implicated in state politics. Given our necessary involvement within politics, the question is not whether we engage with it, but how we do so; even libertarian Marxists like Holloway argue that engagement with the state is inevitable (Holloway 2005: 40). In contrast, the anarchist recommendation of disengagement from the state risks a politics of withdrawal and isolation. There are two related reasons why under our current conditions in particular the Marxist willingness to engage in state politics is preferable to an anarchist position. The first is the dominance of neoliberalism today. Given the strength of neoliberalism since the crisis that it created, there is a strong case for a certain pragmatism in our response. A danger of the prefigurative politics favoured by anarchists is that it dogmatically dictates an a priori exclusion of certain forms of political action. For Marxists, on the other hand, political 10
Description: